HERITABILITY STUDIES IN THE POSTGENOMIC ERA: THE FATAL FLAW IS CONCEPTUAL

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/1745-9125.12060
AuthorRONALD L. SIMONS,CALLIE H. BURT
Published date01 February 2015
Date01 February 2015
HERITABILITY STUDIES IN THE POSTGENOMIC
ERA: THE FATAL FLAW IS CONCEPTUAL
CALLIEH.BURT
1and RONALD L. SIMONS2
1School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Arizona State University
2Department of Sociology, University of Georgia
KEYWORDS: heritability, biosocial criminology, postgenomics, epigenetics, plasticity
In the emerging postgenomic paradigm, we are confronted with a biological world
that is in many ways the opposite of that which has thus far enabled the methodologies
of behavioral genetics. (Charney, 2012: 61)
In our recent article, drawing on advances in the life sciences and echoing the calls
of prominent scholars, including renowned behavioral geneticists (e.g., Rutter, 1997;
Turkheimer, 2011),1we called for an end to heritability studies in criminology and a
recognition of the dubious nature of existing heritability estimates (Burt and Simons,
2014).2We argued that heritability studies are futile for two reasons: 1) Heritability stud-
ies suffer from serious methodological flaws with the overall effect of making estimates
inaccurate and biased toward inflated heritability and deflated shared environmental in-
fluences, and more importantly, 2) the conceptual biological model on which heritability
studies depend—that of identifiably separate effects of genes versus the environment on
phenotype variance—is unsound. The aim of our original article was to educate readers
about both the (often unacknowledged) methodological assumptions and the (outdated)
biological model undergirding heritability studies, evidence that evinces that the heri-
tability study should be superannuated. Our goal was not to foreclose but to reinvigorate
Additional supporting information can be found in the listing for this article in the Wiley Online
Library at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/crim.2015.53.issue-1/issuetoc. [Correction
added on 4 October 2016, after first online publication: The URL http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/
doi/10.1111/crim.2011.53.issue-1/issuetoc was changed to http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/
crim.2015.53.issue-1/issuetoc.]
The authors gratefully acknowledge Kara Hannula, John Laub, D. Wayne Osgood, Alex Piquero,
and Sara Wakefield for valuable comments on earlier drafts of this rejoinder. The arguments pre-
sented herein are entirely those of the authors and do not reflect the views of those who provided
feedback. A longer version of this article is available from the first author. Direct all correspon-
dence to Callie H. Burt, School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Arizona State University, 411
N. Central Ave, Ste. 600, Phoenix, AZ 85004 (e-mail: chburt@asu.edu).
1. Surprisingly, Wright et al. (2015) question our citing of Turkheimer as calling for an end to heri-
tability studies; this rather captious line of attack, consistent with a “hitting it over the head style”
defense, is belied by the facts. For clear quotes repudiating Wright et al.’s claim that Turkheimer is
still advocating for the continued use of heritability studies, see Turkheimer (2011: 598; 2014: 532).
2. When it suits their purpose, Barnes et al. (2014) and Wright et al. (2015) incorrectly broaden our
critique to behavioral genetics and/or biosocial research generally. We have clearly noted through-
out that the heritability study method, including its fallacious technical and conceptual assump-
tions, is the focus of our critique, not behavioral genetics or biosocial work in general.
C2015 American Society of Criminology doi: 10.1111/1745-9125.12060
CRIMINOLOGY Volume 53 Number 1 103–112 2015 103

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT