GOTTA READ KAFKA: NINE REASONS WHY KAFKA IS CRUCIAL FOR THE STUDY OF LAW

Date10 December 2003
Pages89-117
DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(03)31004-X
Published date10 December 2003
AuthorKlaus Mladek
GOTTA READ KAFKA: NINE REASONS
WHY KAFKA IS CRUCIAL FOR THE
STUDY OF LAW
Klaus Mladek
ABSTRACT
The figure of the “Kafkaesque” in law serves often as a stand-in for
something like “perverted justice” and ranks prominently among the legal
profession as a whole. But we should not soothe ourselves with such obvious
clich´es surrounding the “Kafkaesque,” rather we must continue to pursue
the disturbing challenge Kafka poses for the analysis of the law. It is clear
that Kafka’s texts hit a certain nerve of modern law that reacheswell beyond
these familiar punchlines. It is the task of this article to uncover some of the
reasons why Kafka strikes such a strong cord with both legal scholars and
people outside of academia alike.
1. THE PERFORMATIVE POWER OF JUDGMENT
“Judge!Kill!”(H218).JudgingforKafkaalwayscarriesthegravestconsequences.
In Kafka, the order of language passes with ease into an order of reality.Kafka time
and again explores the performative dimension of linguistic acts as he consistently
points to the profound complicity among grammar, thought and judgment. In the
footsteps of Nietzsche’s puns on gerecht (just) and ger¨acht (avenged) or tun (to
do) and ater (perpetrator), Kafka repeatedly exploits and perfects the particular
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society,Volume 31, 89–117
Copyright © 2004 by Elsevier Ltd.
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/doi:10.1016/S1059-4337(03)31004-X
89
90 KLAUS MLADEK
economy of the German language. The shifts and changes from urteilen (to judge)
to verurteilen (to sentence) and aburteilen (to condemn) or from Recht (the law),
Gericht(thecourt)andGerechtigkeitto richten (to judge) or hinrichten (to execute)
populate Kafka’s prose through and through. Judging, sentencing and condemning
are directly correlated to each other as the performance or speech act of passing
down a judgment can have the most devastating effects.
As Kafka’s famous letter to his father from 1919 shows, Kafka views the
authoritarian commands and judgments of his father as far more humiliating than
his actual deeds.1Consider also Kafka’s short story The Judgment (1912) where
the ailing father is suddenly revived and then in a surprising turn sentences his
son “to death by drowning”2(ST 87). The shocked son complies and jumps off a
bridge. Kafka’s stance towards the concept of judgment can be summarized with
a short passage that he wrote in November 1917. In this passage, Kafka envisions
a family counsel in a room through which a continuous flow of fellow men pass,
who witness only fractions of the whole deliberations, but then nevertheless
have to pronounce judgments. Kafka remarks on the judgments they are able to
pass down: “The human judgment about human actions is true and void, that
is at first true and then void.[...] True is the judgment about the word, void the
judgment in itself. Would they have wanted to judge conclusively and truthfully,
they would have become part of the family counsel and thus again unable to
judge. Only the party can truly judge, but as a party it cannot judge. Therefore
there is no possibility of judgment in the world, but only its shimmer” (H 64).
Either one is indifferent and too distant to judge competently or one takes part
of the counsel and hence loses his impartiality. The dilemma of uninformed
distance vs. competent partiality remains irreconcilable. Partial justice confronts
impartial injustice, every “fellow man” (“Mitmensch”) must therefore leave
the room without pronouncing a judgment or become part of indeterminable
deliberations.
Can there even be such as thing as a final decision? Is Kafka’s insistent
challenge for the authority of all judgments. The final decision is always a “mad”
concept for Kafka, it would resemble the impossible closure of the text or the end
of the semiotic chain; to enter the room is to reopen the case, to engage in de-
liberations and thus lose the ability to judge “objectively.” Kafka, as this example
demonstrates, is more interested in the minute process, the spatial configuration
and the situational contexts of judging than in a general theory of judgment.
The gestures of declamation, the mimics of pronouncement, the distance of the
judge to the accused or the sudden change in the perception of the power relation
are consistently much more important for Kafka than deliberate argumentation
or the rational weighing of facts. Kafka invites the legal scholar to analyze the
efficacy of the situational, performative dimension for a legal theory of judgment.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT