“Good-Bye to Nonviolence?”

AuthorWilliam E. Scheuerman
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/10659129211038611
Published date01 December 2022
Date01 December 2022
Subject MatterArticles
https://doi.org/10.1177/10659129211038611
Political Research Quarterly
© 2022 University of Utah
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/10659129211038611
journals.sagepub.com/home/prq
When John Rawls’ (1971, 366) Theory of Justice
described civil disobedience as necessarily nonviolent,
noting that violence was likely “to injure and to hurt” and
therefore inconsistent with politically motivated law-
breaking as a public “mode of address” akin to political
speech, it codified what soon came to be widely viewed
as the standard liberal view. Rawls rejected the spiritually
oriented pacifisms of Mahatma Gandhi and Martin Luther
King, endorsing nonviolent lawbreaking not on the basis
of an “abhorrence of the use of force in principle,” but
instead because it was congruent with civility, moral con-
scientiousness, and basic respect for the law. Nonviolence
provided evidence of “one’s sincerity” while buttressing
the idea of “disobedience to law within the limits of fidel-
ity to law,” for Rawls (1971, 366–67) (and his liberal con-
temporaries) an essential feature of civil disobedience.
Although Rawls had little to say either about the political
contours of nonviolence or its conceptual parameters, he
characterized it as fortifying civil disobedience’s core
elements. Protestors could legitimately “warn and admon-
ish” those who had violated basic liberties and common
liberal principles of justice (Rawls 1971, 366). But, Rawls
added, they should not threaten to harm anyone.
Not surprisingly, Rawls and other Anglophone liberals
from the 1960s and ’70s are usually interpreted as having
refurbished the idea of nonviolent civil disobedience, as
previously advocated and practiced by Gandhi, King, and
many others. That standard reading has recently provided
a launching pad for a body of theoretical reflection that
challenges strictly nonviolent civil disobedience’s privi-
leged normative status. To be sure, some, typically more
radical, voices during the 1960s and ’70s already sug-
gested the possibility of violent civil disobedience
(Morreall [1976] 1991; Zinn [1968] 2002). Yet, even if
the marriage of nonviolence to civil disobedience occa-
sionally seemed strained, today it appears to be in sham-
bles, with the once marginal idea of politically motivated,
possibly legitimate, violent lawbreaking now common-
place among theorists of political obligation. Some still
view violent lawbreaking as falling under the conceptual
rubric of civil disobedience (Allen 2009; Brownlee 2012;
Celikates 2016a, 2016b; Moraro 2019; Simmons 2005,
2015; Welchman 2001); others embrace uncivil disobedi-
ence and related terms (e.g., resistance) in part because
they hope to justify some types of political violence.1
Whatever their particular terminological preferences,
they target Rawls and worry that liberalism’s marriage of
nonviolence to civil disobedience founders on its failure
0
38611PRQXXX10.1177/10659129211038611Political Research QuarterlyScheuerman
2
022
1Indiana University Bloomington, USA
Corresponding Author:
William E. Scheuerman, Indiana University Bloomington,
Bloomington, IN 47405-7000, USA.
Email: wscheuer@indiana.edu
“Good-Bye to Nonviolence?”
William E. Scheuerman1
Abstract
John Rawls and other liberals from the 1960s and ’70s are usually interpreted as having refurbished the idea of
nonviolent civil disobedience, as practiced by Gandhi, King, and many others. That standard reading has recently
provided a launching pad for a growing body of critical theoretical reflection that challenges strictly nonviolent civil
disobedience’s privileged normative status. Here I offer a revisionist account of both liberal (and especially) Rawlsian
nonviolent disobedience and recent attempts to supersede it. Recent critics occasionally miss their targets: the main
differences separating Rawls from the critics revolve around competing empirical assessments of contemporary liberal
societies and rival accounts of political violence. Rawls and other liberals, in fact, provided normative space for
limited forms of “violent” lawbreaking, when resulting typically not in injuries to other persons but perhaps damage
to property. The debate about nonviolent vs. violent political illegality needs to pay closer attention to the difficult
issue of how best to understand and define political violence. Although we may need to provide normative space
under unjust conditions for limited types of violence (e.g., property damage), substantial grounds remain for principally
favoring lawbreaking that avoids injuring or violating persons.
Keywords
political violence, civil disobedience, resistance, John Rawls, liberalism
2022, Vol. 75(4) 1284–1296
Article

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT