Fact, Theory, and Democratic Theory

AuthorDavid C. Paris
Published date01 June 1987
Date01 June 1987
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/106591298704000202
Subject MatterArticles
FACT,
THEORY,
AND
DEMOCRATIC
THEORY
DAVID
C.
PARIS
Hamilton
College
NE
of the
persistent
problems
in
contemporary
democratic
theory
~
has
been
to
specify
the
proper
relationship(s)
of
democratic
ideals
to
actual
political
practices.
This
problem
is
often
expressed
in
the
form
of
a
dilemma
between
the
demands
of
democratic
ideals
and
empiri-
cal
constraints
on
their
realization.
For
example,
Margolis
argues
that, &dquo;It
may
not
be
possible
to
develop
a
theory
of liberal
democracy
which
is
com-
patible
with
both
the
empirically
demonstrated
capabilities
of
the
citizenry
and
the
theoretically
demonstrated
necessity
of
preserving
liberal
values&dquo;
(1979:
93).
There
seems
to
be
an
inevitable
trade-off
between
making
democratic
theory
realistic
or
practical,
on
the
one
hand,
and
fulfilling
democratic
ideals,
on
the
other.
If
we
allow
empirical
research
to
constrain
our
ideals
by
leading
us
to
underestimate
what
is
possible,
then
we
may
undercut
those
ideals
and
fail
to
use
them
to
guide
us
in
improving
the
political
system.
If
we
insulate
our
ideals
from
empirical
evidence
and
anal-
ysis,
then
we
may
be
merely
building
elegant
but
wholly
unrealistic
and
useless
analytical
systems.
This
problem
is
not
unique
to
democratic
theory.
Any
ideals
or
ideolo-
gies
simultaneously
express
the
way
someone
thinks the
world
does
work,
should
work,
and
even
might
work
if
social
and
political
behavior
and
in-
stitutions
were
changed.
The
problem
arises
when
the
world
does
not
con-
form
to
these
expectations.
In
the
face
of
discrepancies
between
ideals
and
reality,
one
might
cling
to
the
former
believing
that
the
contrary
evidence
is
merely
an
aberration
or
a
misinterpretation.
Or,
more
aggressively,
it
might
be
demanded
that
the
world
itself
be
changed
to
conform
more
closely
to
the
ideal
pattern.
On
the
other
hand,
the
collision
of
ideals
and
facts
may
prompt
an
adjustment
in
what
one
believes
can
and
should
be
done.
This
latter
strategy
is
often
what
is
anticipated
by
the
injunction
to
be &dquo;realis-
tic&dquo;
in
political
and
moral
affairs,
i.e.,
to
temper
or
modify
our
moral
ex-
pectations
on
the
basis
of
a
clear
view
of
empirical
evidence
and
practical
possibility.
The
appeal
to
realism
is
thus
not
unique
to
arguments
in
democratic
theory
but
may
be
used
for
or
against
relatively
narrow
poli-
cies
or
the
broadest
world
views.’
1
The
power
of
the
appeal
to
realism
in
political
argument
derives
from
at
least
two
sources,
one
evidentiary,
the
other
practical.
Realism
means
both
recognizing
relevant
empirical
considerations
and
responding
to
them
in
a
practical
way.
First,
empirical
evidence
can
advance
or
undercut
a
Received:
October
3,
1985
Revision
Received:
April
7,
1986
Accepted
for
Publication:
April
28,
1986
1
For
example,
it
is
often
argued
that
Marxists
have
an
unrealistic
view
of
human
nature
and
the
possibilities
of
technology
and
social
organization.
216
political
argument
or
theory,
or
even
occasionally
adjudicate
between
two
competing
arguments
or
theories.
For
example,
the
psychological
research
presented
in
the
Brown
vs.
Board
case
-
however
sound
or
unsound
it
ac-
tually
was -
did
help
to
undercut
the
claim
that
separate
but
equal
schools
could
be
maintained.
One
need
not
be
an
ethical
relativist
to
believe
that
there
is
a
greater
possibility
of
reaching
some
agreement
on
empirical
matters
than
on
vague
or
contested
normative
claims.
It
is
tempting
to
seek
just
that
piece
of
evidence
which
defeats
or
clinches
an
argument.
Second,
if
political
arguments
or
theories
are
to
be
more
than
mere
abstractions
or
analytic
exercises,
then
empirical
information
is
valuable
in
suggesting
how
the
argument
or
theory
may
be
applied
to
practical
concerns.
This
infor-
mation
is
not
only
valuable
as
a
means
of
getting
theory
to
guide
practice
but
also
as
a
means
of
probing
the
practical
limits
of
theoretical
schemes.
Theories
or
arguments
must
not
only
speak
to
the
world;
they
must
in
some
sense
answer
to
it.
The
clash
between
ideals
and
empirical
evidence
arises
in
democratic
theory
as
a
result
of
the
consideration
of
the
actual
political
practices
of
modern
Western
democracies.
Revisions
of
democratic
theory
undertaken
by
Schumpeter,
Dahl,
Truman,
and
others
(Holden
1973:
chs.
5-6;
Mar-
golis
1979:
95-124)
have
attempted
to
alleviate
the
apparent
tensions
be-
tween
some
(ill-defined) &dquo;classical
ideal&dquo;
of
democratic
politics
and
actual
political
practices.
Although
there
is
no
single
revisionist
theory
-
or
for
that
matter
any one
&dquo;classical&dquo;
or
participatory
theory2
-
there
remains
a
consensus
among
democratic
theorists
that
democratic
ideals
must
come
to
terms
with
the
findings
of
empirical
research
into
political
practices.
A
realistic
democratic
theory
requires
a
clearer
view
of
how
central
democratic
ideals
can
be
maintained
in
large-scale,
complex
societies,
e.g.,
through
elections
and
interest
groups,
without
unrealistic
demands
on
citizen
com-
petence
and
participation
(Kelso
1978:
13ff.).
The
power
of
this
appeal
to
realism
was
especially
apparent
in
debates
between
pluralists
and
participa-
tory
democrats.
The
charge
that
revised
theory
in
its
various
forms
had
compromised
democratic
ideals
was
countered
by
the
charge
that
participa-
tory
democrats’
theories
were
unrealistic.
Although
some
consessions
could
be
made
to
calls
for
increases
in
participation
and
greater
material
equal-
ity
(Dahl
1970),
participatory
democracy
was
dismissed
as
unrealistic, &dquo;an
impossible
ideal,
a
Quixotic
dream&dquo;
(Pennock
1979:
468).3
3
The
purpose
of
this
essay
is
to
examine
the
methodological
issue
of
what
constitutes
a
&dquo;realistic&dquo;
approach
to
democratic
theory,
i.e.,
to
ask
how
democratic
ideals
can
come
to
terms
with
the
facts
of
political
life.
This
is
a
methodological
issue
because
it
involves
ascertaining
what
evidence
is
relevant
to
a
(realistic)
democratic
theory,
how
it
is
obtained,
and
above
all
how
it
is
evaluated
and
used.
This
issue
will
be
examined
by
pointing
2
Pateman
(1970)
argues
that
the
"classical
ideal"
of
the
citizen
criticized
in
revised
democratic
theories
is
either
a
strawman
or
a
myth.
This
may
be
true;
however,
there
is
some
reason-
able
notion
of
the
(ideal)
democratic
citizen
which
seems
hardly
applicable
to
contem-
porary
societies.
See
Margolis
(1979:
ch.
1)
and
Mansbridge
(1982:
chs.
1, 2).
3
Indeed,
some
have
argued
that
it
may
even
be
dangerous
(Huntington
1975).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT