Discounting and welfare evaluation of policies

Published date01 October 2017
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jpet.12266
AuthorAnna Rubinchik,Jean‐François Mertens
Date01 October 2017
Received: 27 May2016 Accepted: 2 August 2017
DOI: 10.1111/jpet.12266
ARTICLE
Discounting and welfare evaluation of policies
Jean-François Mertens1Anna Rubinchik2
1CORE,Université Catholique de Louvain
2Departmentof Economics, University of Haifa
Theauthors wish to thank the seminar partici-
pantsat Bar-Ilan University, participants of the
conferenceorganized by the Society for Benefit-
CostAnalysis in Washington, DC, and the two
anonymousreferees for their useful comments;
S.Coate and L. Kotlikoff for insightful discussions,
aswell as S. BenYosef.The paper has been sub-
stantiallyrevised since the first author passed
away.The scientific responsibility rests with the
secondauthor.
Jean-FrançoisMertens, CORE, Université
Catholiquede Louvain, 34, Voie du Roman-
Pays,B-1348 Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgique
(jfm@core.ucl.ac.be).
AnnaRubinchik, Department of Economics,
Universityof Haifa, Mount Carmel, Haifa 31905,
Israel(arubinchik@econ.haifa.ac.il).
We start with the premise that if policy discounting is to have any
welfare relevance, one has to accept it being a derivative of a social
welfare function (SWF). We show that if that derivative is to have
a net present value (NPV) form, then the baseline allocation must
be stationary. In addition, we show that at a stationary baseline in
an overlappinggenerations growth economy, the intergenerationally
fair discount rate equals the growth rate of per-capita consump-
tion, which is, roughly, 2% for the United States. This differs from
the interest rate, even in the golden rule equilibrium, unless popu-
lation growth is null. The last result is based on the main theorem in
Mertensand Rubinchik (2012) and is demonstrated for a policy space
that might naturally arise in applications.
1INTRODUCTION
Our main goal is to reconcile two approaches to policy evaluation.One is the benefit-cost analysis used by practitioners
and the other is the welfare-based criterion commonly used by academic economists. We show that the two might be
consistent, and when they are the latter yields a clear choice of parameters for the former.
“Benefit-cost analysis is a primary tool used for regulatory analysis.” This statement appears in Circular A-4 of the
U.S. Office of Management and Budget (OMB; 2003, p. 2), which was developed to reviewand coordinate regulatory
programs of the U.S.Federal agencies.1
As is well-known (cf. Mishan, 1976), the classical “efficiency” rationale used in cost-benefit analysis (CBA) is the
Kaldor–Hicks criterion, which is based on the total monetized net benefit, and thus is seemingly independent of dis-
tribution of benefits. The same applies to projects that span several years, in which case the regulators are to use a
discounted value of future net benefits, and hence to evaluate the net present value (NPV) of the monetized benefits
using the interest rate for discounting.2
CBA has a major advantage over manyother possible ways to evaluate merits of a public project: it provides a clear
quantifiable criterion for policy evaluation (whenever full monetization is feasible) that is based on willingness to pay
(WTP) and cost of resources, which are fundamental to determining an optimal allocation in a classical sense. There are
1Inaccordance with sect. 2(b) of Executive Order 12866, “Regulatory Planning and Review.”
2U.S.Office of Management and Budget, 2003, p. 31–36.
Journal of Public Economic Theory.2017;19:903–920. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/jpet c
2017 Wiley Periodicals,Inc. 903
904 MERTENSAND RUBINCHIK
some caveats, however,that make us want to come back to the welfare foundations, i.e., evaluating policies based on a
well-defined (or evenaxiomatized) societal objective. As Hammond (1985) puts it,
The compensation test compares different individuals'monetary gains and losses by treating all incre-
mental dollars equally. There is no denyingthat such comparisons are actually very specific interper-
sonal comparisons of utility,with utility effectively measured in monetary units, and all individuals'incre-
mental dollars being regarded as equally valuable, no matter what the distribution of income may be.
One might want to be more careful about such interpersonal comparisons, when the losers and winners belong
to different generations. Even the OMB Circular encourages the regulators to analyze the distributional effects of
the proposed action in addition to the standard CBA, as “[b]enefits and costs of a regulation may also be distributed
unevenly overtime, perhaps spanning several generations.”
This is where the classical welfare foundations could help to identify the underlying “trade-offs” and evaluate them
in a systematic way.
The merits of using an explicit welfare function for policy analysis havebeen advocated by Drèze and Stern (1987).
Our ability to meaningfully argue about choosing such a function dates back to the seminal contribution of Harsanyi
(1955).3
Let us now illustrateHammond's claim that any policy evaluation based on the Kaldor–Hicks criterion embeds some
distributional judgment. If we takethe utilitarian view, it pins down welfare weights, which are equilibrium-dependent,
known as Negishi weights (Negishi, 1960). Such weights are not always easy to justify,especially when any agent can
consume only a subset of all goods in the economy, as is true in an overlapping generations (OG)world. The latter
assumption is crucial to express the passage of time: all consumer goods are dated goods; not all of them are available
at the same point in time.
Example (A toy OG model). There are three different private goods: apples (c1), pheasants (c2) and salt (s), and one public
good (g). There are three agents standing for generations A, B, C (B overlaps with A and C). Toavoid dealing with infinite past
and future and to prevent autarchic (inefficient) equilibria, we let salt play the role of money. The first generation is endowed
with salt; none of the first two generations derives utility from it, but the last generation enjoys it, which representsthe value
of salt “in future transactions” that are cut off from this model. As for the public good, the first generationlikes it, the second
generation does not carefor it, but the last generation hates it. To be specific, assume:
uA(c1A,g)= c1Ag
g+c1A
,(1)
uB(c1B,c
2B)=𝜗c1B+c2B,(2)
uC(c2C,s
C,g)=c2C2g+sC.(3)
A owns all the salt (𝜔s),B owns all the apples (𝜔1>𝜔s
𝜗), and C owns all the pheasants (𝜔2>𝜔
s). All agents act as price takers
(replicate the economyif needed). Only private goods are traded. Then the markets should clear at prices p1=𝜗for apples and
p2=ps=1for pheasants and salt. Indeed, then the demand for apples is c1A=𝜔s
𝜗from agent A, while agent B is indifferent
between any bundle on his budget line, hence c1B=𝜔11
𝜗c2B; therefore, market clearing in the apple market implies that
c2B=𝜔s. At these prices, agent C is also indifferent between any bundle on his budget line so c2C=𝜔2sC;hence,market
clearing in the pheasant market yields sC=𝜔s. Thus, the marketallocation is (for some fixed initial g)
(c1A,c
2A,s
A)=𝜔s
𝜗,0,0,
(c1B,c
2B,s
B)=𝜔1𝜔s
𝜗,𝜔s,0,
(c1C,c
2C,s
C)=(0,𝜔2𝜔s,𝜔s).
3Foran overview of the related literature, please refer to Mertens and Rubinchik (2012). Here, let us mention one of the most recent relevant contributions,
Fleurbaeyand Zuber (2015), who analyze the implications of equity considerations on social discounting.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT