DEVELOPMENT AND FRACTURE OF A DISCIPLINE: LEGACIES OF THE SCHOOL OF CRIMINOLOGY AT BERKELEY

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/1745-9125.12081
Date01 November 2015
AuthorJOHANN KOEHLER
Published date01 November 2015
DEVELOPMENT AND FRACTURE OF A DISCIPLINE:
LEGACIES OF THE SCHOOL OF CRIMINOLOGY AT
BERKELEY
JOHANN KOEHLER
Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program, School of Law, University of
California—Berkeley
KEYWORDS: history of criminology, professionalization, radical criminology,
neo-institutional theory, legitimacy, institutional logic
In the early twentieth century, the University of California—Berkeley opened its
doors to police professionals for instruction in “police science.” This program ulti-
mately developed into the full-fledged School of Criminology, whose graduates helped
shape American criminology and criminal justice until well into the 1970s. Scholar-
ship at the School of Criminology eventually fractured into three distinct traditions:
“Administrative criminology” applied scientific methods in pursuit of refining law en-
forcement practices, “law and society” coupled legal scholarship with social scientific
methods, and “radical criminology” combined Marxist critiques of the state with com-
munity activism. Those scientific traditions relied on competing epistemic premises and
normative aspirations, and they drew legitimacy from different sources. Drawing on
oral histories and archival data permits a neo-institutional analysis of how each of
these criminological traditions emerged, acquired stability, and subsided. The Berke-
ley School of Criminology provides fertile ground to examine trends in the develop-
ment of criminal justice as a profession, criminology as a discipline and its place in
elite universities, the uncoupling of criminology from law and society scholarship, and
criminal justice policy’s disenchantment with the academy. These legacies highlight
how the development of modern criminology and the professionalization of American
law enforcement find precedent in events that originate at Berkeley.
Additional supporting information can be found in the listing for this article in the Wiley Online
Library at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/crim.2015.53.issue-4/issuetoc.
The author kindly thanks the interviewees for participating in this research, Brendan Dooley for
help with the American Society of Criminology’s Oral History Project, and the librarians at the
Bancroft Library of the University of California—Berkeley and at the Radzinowicz Library of
the Institute of Criminology, University of Cambridge, for their invaluable assistance in securing
the necessary archival materials. The author also thanks the Jurisprudence and Social Policy Pro-
gram and the Coblentz Civil Rights Endowment for generously supporting this research. Con-
structive insights provided by Calvin Morrill, Keramet Reiter, Ashley Rubin, Jonathan Simon,
Tobias Smith, Franklin Zimring, and the anonymous reviewers greatly improved the article. Ear-
lier versions of this research were presented at the 2013 annual conference of the Western Society
of Criminology, held in Berkeley, California, and at the 2013 annual meeting of the American
Society of Criminology, held in Atlanta, Georgia. Direct correspondence to Johann Koehler, Ju-
risprudence and Social Policy Program, School of Law, University of California—Berkeley, 2240
Piedmont Ave., Berkeley, CA 94720 (e-mail: jkoehler@berkeley.edu).
C2015 American Society of Criminology doi: 10.1111/1745-9125.12081
CRIMINOLOGY Volume Number 513–544 2015 513
514 KOEHLER
In the early part of the twentieth century, the University of California—Berkeley
(herein often “the University” or “Berkeley”) became the site for an innovative experi-
ment in the realization of a Progressive Era project. In 1916, the first chief of the Berkeley
Police Department, August Vollmer, pined for a new approach to the administration of
law enforcement based on modern scientific techniques. He called for a School of Crimi-
nology (herein often the “School”) for the special training of police officers at the neigh-
boring university, citing its establishment as “a requirement of the times” (Vollmer and
Schneider, 1916: 878). Those times necessitated a consideration of the role of law en-
forcement as a profession, and Vollmer fancied himself as its champion. The legacy that
Vollmer left behind in his efforts to imbue criminology with the legitimacy and trappings
of a traditional academic discipline and profession is a story of fits, starts, and frustra-
tions. During the course of 60 years, criminology at Berkeley experienced a tumultuous
rise and fall. It rose to a preeminent position in both the establishment of criminology
and the professionalization of justice administration, and it then descended to a position
of notoriety in the policy sphere in the period immediately preceding its dissolution once
liberal scholarship on law enforcement reform had been displaced to the School of Law.
Indeed, before the School of Criminology’s dissolution in 1976, it had come to be recog-
nized as the embodiment of a generally prevailing illegitimacy endemic to criminal justice
studies in elite institutions of higher learning.
The School of Criminology at Berkeley therefore provides fertile ground to examine
important trends in the development of criminal justice as a profession; the legitimacy of
criminology as a discipline and its place on elite university campuses; the uncoupling of
criminology from law and society; and criminal justice policy’s eventual disenchantment
with the academy. This article charts all four of these trends, and in so doing, it demon-
strates that the development of criminology and the professionalization of American law
enforcement find precedent in events that originate at Berkeley.
The School owed its founding to the efforts of Vollmer and his students, who doggedly
pursued an agenda of modernization in law enforcement without providing an argument
for the form that such modernization should take beyond rudimentary appeals to techno-
cratic ideals. They formulated a vocationally oriented “administrative criminology” that
was focused on improving the administration of justice, but this departed from the ap-
proach to criminological knowledge production practiced elsewhere in the country. The
failure to specify whether administrative criminology was a vocational or an academic en-
terprise also created ruptures with the institutional support on which criminology could
rely in its early years. Thus, the absence of a coherent institutional logic in administrative
criminology resulted in a gradual fragmentation and stratification of police education into
various groups without a shared value set.
By the 1960s, the School witnessed a failure to maintain cohesion between the academic
and the professional members of the discipline, and support for the School’s existence
on the Berkeley campus diminished. Shortly thereafter, the Russell Sage Foundation
launched a program of supporting scholarship that connected law with social science and
funded the establishment of Berkeley’s Center for the Study of Law and Society (CSLS).
Many faculty members from the School of Criminology would be closely connected with
that Center, and it soon arose to prominence as a producer of “law and society” scholar-
ship (Wheeler, 1994). Contemporaneously, the School expanded its faculty and incubated
“radical criminology,” which was characterized both by a preoccupation with inequalities
of power and class and by a commitment to social activism in the neighboring community.
LEGACIES OF THE SCHOOL OF CRIMINOLOGY AT BERKELEY 515
The three intellectual strands of scholarship represented within the School, administra-
tive and radical criminologies and law and society, were not always harmonious; each
professed a different set of epistemic premises about the nature and goals of criminolog-
ical scholarship, and they derived their legitimacy from different sources, depending on
the institutional field they defined for the knowledge they produced.
THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK
Previously, the story of the Berkeley School has been told as a case study in either “the
limits of academic tolerance” (Geis, 1995, p. 277) or as a casualty of academic politics
(Morn, 1995), or it has been studied with the purpose of piercing through the fog of ac-
rimony to clarify who was to blame for its dissolution (Schwendinger and Schwendinger,
2014).1To do so, the interactions among scholars, research groups, and university offices
are represented as though the dissolution of the School was a political response to satisfy
individual or academic imperatives, such as the School’s increasing reorientation away
from providing professionally trained law enforcement officials ready to fill the needs of
justice administration.
This analysis of the School is oriented toward a different purpose altogether. Apply-
ing a neo-institutional theoretical framework clarifies how criminology failed to articu-
late a system of values and norms around which professionals working in the field could
coalesce, and this failure resulted in continuing skepticism and bewilderment about the
appropriateness and function of universities in facilitating law enforcement profession-
alization more broadly. Moreover, the institutional logics of the various and competing
scientific research programs were shaped and managed within the organizational con-
fines of the School so as to project an institutional identity of legitimacy. However, be-
cause the criminological traditions in question relied on competing institutional logics, the
School is therefore theorized as part of a complex web of intellectual projects and bureau-
cratic constraints, and it is viewed through multiple levels of units of analysis (compris-
ing individual scholars, cohesive research programs, intellectual fields, and institutional
imperatives).
The following departs from previous analyses by eschewing a functionalist interpreta-
tion of the viability of a scientific research program or profession by reference to how
well it satisfies exigencies such as the need to provide efficient solutions (including, for
example, the School’s ability to produce effective police officers). It also departs from
an approach to the sociology of science associated with work by Bourdieu (1988, 2004)
and Collins (1998). Those frameworks view the intellectual field as part of a competition
for the scarce resource of scholarly attention, thus giving rise to Collins’s claim about the
axiomatic coexistence of only three to six “schools” of thought at a given time. This frame-
work is deficient in two respects. First, as noted by Lamont (2001), it imagines scholars as
rational actors who seek to maximize their position within the intellectual field’s attention
space. It thus discounts the many possible reasons that may explain a scientific research
program’s development and survival beyond the ability of scholars within that program to
1. I owe much to the impressive exposition of the School’s history found in these aforementioned
efforts. However, as will be explained in detail, they undertheorize the School by overlooking how
its scientific research programs are themselves distinct units of analysis, and they elide an analysis
of the search for legitimacy engaged by the institutions in question.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT