DEMONSTRATING THE VALIDITY OF TWIN RESEARCH IN CRIMINOLOGY

AuthorJOHN PAUL WRIGHT,JOSEPH L. NEDELEC,ERIC J. CONNOLLY,J. C. BARNES,JOSEPH A. SCHWARTZ,KEVIN M. BEAVER,BRIAN B. BOUTWELL
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/1745-9125.12049
Published date01 November 2014
Date01 November 2014
DEMONSTRATING THE VALIDITY OF TWIN
RESEARCH IN CRIMINOLOGY
J. C. BARNES,1JOHN PAUL WRIGHT,1,6 BRIAN B. BOUTWELL,2
JOSEPH A. SCHWARTZ,3ERIC J. CONNOLLY,4
JOSEPH L. NEDELEC,1and KEVIN M. BEAVER5,6
1School of Criminal Justice, University of Cincinnati
2School of Social Work, Saint Louis University
3School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, University of Nebraska at Omaha
4Criminal Justice Department, Pennsylvania State University, Abington
5College of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Florida State University
6Center for Social and Humanities Research, King Abdulaziz University,
Jeddah
KEYWORDS: assumptions, behavior genetics, biosocial, empirical, quantitative, twins
In a recent article published in Criminology, Burt and Simons (2014) claimed that
the statistical violations of the classical twin design render heritability studies useless.
Claiming quantitative genetics is “fatally flawed” and describing the results generated
from these models as “preposterous,” Burt and Simons took the unprecedented step
to call for abandoning heritability studies and their constituent findings. We show that
their call for an “end to heritability studies” was premature, misleading, and entirely
without merit. Specifically, we trace the history of behavioral genetics and show that 1)
the Burt and Simons critique dates back 40 years and has been subject to a broad array
of empirical investigations, 2) the violation of assumptions in twin models does not in-
validate their results, and 3) Burt and Simons created a distorted and highly misleading
portrait of behavioral genetics and those who use quantitative genetic approaches.
“The flaws of twin studies are not fatal, but rather seem no worse (and may be better)
than the flaws of the typical causal study that relies on observational data.”
(Felson, 2012: ii)
Behavioral genetic research has existed for more than 100 years (Maxson, 2007). Since
its inception, it has been a lightning rod of criticism, especially by scholars who are inal-
terably opposed to linking biology with behavior. Over this time, numerous critics (e.g.,
Additional supporting information can be found in the listing for this article in the Wiley Online
Library at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/crim.2014.52.issue-4/issuetoc.
We wish to thank each of the five anonymous reviewers for their scholarly insight. In addition, we
would like to acknowledge Mara Brendgen, Francis Cullen, Lisabeth DiLalla, Christopher Fer-
guson, Judith Rich Harris, Kenneth Kendler, Terrie Moffitt, Christopher Patrick, Steven Pinker,
Stephen Tibbetts, Catherine Tuvblad, and Anthony Walsh for their comments, suggestions, and
feedback on previous drafts of this article. Of course, all errors and omissions are ours and ours
alone. Direct correspondence to J. C. Barnes, School of Criminal Justice, University of Cincinnati,
Cincinnati, OH 45221 (e-mail: jc.barnes@uc.edu).
C2014 American Society of Criminology doi: 10.1111/1745-9125.12049
CRIMINOLOGY Volume 52 Number 4 588–626 2014 588
VALIDITY OF TWIN RESEARCH 589
Joseph, 2004; Lewontin, Rose, and Kamin, 1984) have leveled various charges against
twin designs and the assumptions on which they are based. Beginning in the 1970s, polit-
ically motivated critics of behavioral genetics launched an all-out crusade against such
methods, the findings emanating from them, and even on the researchers themselves
(Segerstr˚
ale, 2000). These critics called for an end to the idea that biology had anything
to do with behavior, noting that sociobiology was a “dangerous idea.” Relying heavily
on anecdotes, opinions, and the occasional mathematical example, critics of behavioral
genetics were unrelenting in their attack.
In response, a small but growing force of behavioral geneticists, statisticians, and other
scholars launched a prolonged effort to collect larger samples of twins, other geneti-
cally related relatives, and adoptees. They used these samples to test, retest, and re-
fine behavioral genetic models. Throughout the 1980s, behavioral geneticists published
study after study documenting the robustness of behavioral genetic methods, especially
those designed to assess heritability (Floderus-Myrhed, Pederson, and Rasmuson, 1980;
Paul, 1980; Pederson et al., 1985; Rice, Cloninger, and Reich, 1980; Rushton et al., 1986;
Scarr, Scarf, and Weinberg, 1980). These studies quickly multiplied, eventually leading
behavioral geneticists to “lose their identity” because they became so integrated within
psychology and other fields (Scarr, 1987). By the end of the 1980s, the war was over with
a large body of research findings supporting the general thrust of behavioral genetic mod-
eling (Plomin and Bergeman, 1991). As time went on, isolated critics (e.g., Joseph, 2004)
emerged only to be greeted by even more empirical evidence in favor of the validity of
the findings stemming from behavioral genetic studies. Today, behavioral genetic stud-
ies inform a broad range of fields, including medicine, psychiatry, psychology, education,
and even criminology. Summarizing the large body of behavioral genetic findings that had
emerged prior to 2002, Pinker (2002: 374) observed:
The results [of heritability studies] come out roughly the same no matter what is
measured or how it is measured. . .. All of this translates into substantial heritability
values, generally between .25 and .75. A conventional summary is that about half of
the variation in intelligence, personality, and life outcomes is heritable.
The collective body of biosocial evidence thus directly aligns with the “reality” of find-
ings from every other discipline. Broadly speaking, biosocial criminologists have found
that approximately 50 percent of the variance in antisocial phenotypes can be attributed
to genetic influences, followed by unique environmental influences and, to a lesser extent,
common (or shared) environmental influences (Beaver, 2013; Ferguson, 2010; Moffitt,
2005).
These findings, and others, however, find themselves once again imperiled. A recent
publication in Criminology by Burt and Simons (2014; hereafter Burt and Simons) called
for criminologists to abandon heritability studies and effectively to jettison them from
the discipline. In doing so, Burt and Simons called for a de facto form of censorship.
Their logic was straightforward: Twin studies are fatally flawed, the findings cannot be
trusted, old findings should be placed on the scrapheap of scientific history, and new find-
ings only reify what is known to be untrustworthy. As a result, no bona fide criminolog-
ical journal should publish twin-based research moving forward. Joining history’s critics
(Joseph, 2004), Burt and Simons critiqued heritability studies and those who use behav-
ioral genetics models. Although their arguments were multifaceted, they bear a striking
590 BARNES ET AL.
resemblance to the arguments leveled against behavioral geneticists in the 1970s. Even so,
their argument was powerful, emotionally appealing, and seductive, especially for those
uninformed about behavioral genetics and for those ideologically opposed to biology.
Burt and Simons argued that behavioral genetic methods are fundamentally flawed
because violation of “crucial assumptions” and “technical limitations” inevitably leads
to upwardly biased estimates of heritability and to downwardly biased estimates of the
common environment. Burt and Simons detailed a series of methodological arguments
against heritability studies, arguing, for instance, that violations of the equal environ-
ments assumption (EEA; “the environment of MZ co-twins is no more similar than that
of DZ co-twins”) are “flatly contradicted by both empirical evidence and common sense”
(p. 231).1Indeed, they even told us “behavioral geneticists acknowledged that the EEA
was invalid” (p. 232). Yet the EEA was just one of many behavioral genetic assumptions
attacked by Burt and Simons. Because twin research rests on critical assumptions, as-
sumptions Burt and Simons argued are always violated, findings from heritability studies
are “biologically nonsensical” (p. 225). After purportedly scrutinizing prior studies, Burt
and Simons went on to brand entire bodies of carefully collected and meticulously ana-
lyzed scientific evidence as useless, and even “preposterous” (p. 236). Burt and Simons
then proceeded to tell readers that behavioral genetic findings are “implausible” and that
behavioral genetic research rests on a “dubious foundation” (p. 223). In the end, they
claimed to have exposed the critical flaws of behavioral genetic research.
But did they expose any fundamental flaws of behavioral genetics? Did they present the
readers of Criminology a fair and impartial assessment of behavioral genetics research?
Did they delve deeply into the vast body of behavioral genetic literature, into the technical
aspects of assumption violation, biased parameter estimates, and erroneous conclusions?
Or, instead, did they join past critics and reify arguments already shown to be unsubstan-
tiated by empirical evidence? Clearly, as even Burt and Simons recognized, “most of the
arguments” in their article “are not original” (p. 225). Does repeating arguments origi-
nally proposed in the 1970s, and refuted shortly thereafter, make them relevant today? In
short, can we believe Burt and Simons have ascertained unbiased and definitive proof that
behavioral genetic models are wrong? Have they done something no other statistician,
theorist, or behavioral geneticist in the last four decades has been able to accomplish?
In the following pages, we show that the criticisms of behavioral genetic models ad-
vanced by Burt and Simons have not only been answered by dozens of prior studies but
also that they are wrong. We show this mathematically, with an in-depth examination
of the basis of twin designs, with our own simulation models that directly illustrate the
impact of violating assumptions on heritability estimates, and by examining 61 empirical
studies that have tested one of the “critical assumptions” pointed out by Burt and Simons:
the EEA. In the end, we show that the violations of behavioral genetic assumptions hardly
qualify as “fatal flaws” that can be used as a justification to abandon heritability studies.
Indeed, the evidence to this fact is overwhelming and should reduce any confidence read-
ers extended to the Burt and Simons article.
If showing mathematically that Burt and Simons grossly exaggerated their claims is
not sufficient, we then examine the scholarship underpinning their critique of heritability
studies. We show, in detail, where they misquoted scholars, where they misrepresented
1. MZ =monozygotic and DZ =dizygotic.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT