Deliberate with the Enemy? Polarization, Social Identity, and Attitudes toward Disagreement

Published date01 March 2018
Date01 March 2018
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/1065912917721371
Subject MatterArticles
https://doi.org/10.1177/1065912917721371
Political Research Quarterly
2018, Vol. 71(1) 3 –18
© 2017 University of Utah
Reprints and permissions:
sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/1065912917721371
journals.sagepub.com/home/prq
Article
When citizens and accountable officials disagree, and also
recognize that they are seeking deliberative agreement, they
remain willing to argue with one another with the aim of
achieving provisionally justifiable policies that they can
recognize as such.
—Gutmann and Thompson (1996)
There’s nothing short of Trump shooting my daughter in the
street and my grandchildren—there is nothing and nobody
that’s going to dissuade me from voting for Trump.
—Lola Butler, Donald Trump supporter
(quoted from Barbaro, Parker, and Martin 2016)
During the run-up to the 2012 Presidential election, the
radio show This American Life produced an episode on
polarized politics titled “Red States Blue State.” In one
particularly evocative scene, interviewer Lisa Pollack
profiles Frank Mills and Ron Sexton. The two men were
close friends who repeatedly discussed political issues on
the phone. This is until, as Pollack describes on-air, “Ron
urged Frank to support a Republican candidate for
Congress. Frank balked. Didn’t Ron know he supported
Democrats?
Frank Mills: And he (Ron) said, “Who did you vote for for
president?” And I said, “I voted for Obama.”
Lisa Pollak: Apparently this had not come up before.
Frank Mills: And then he said, “You must be a Socialist.”
Lisa Pollak: He said this seriously or jokingly?
Frank Mills: No, seriously. “You must be a Socialist.” And I
said, “How can you make that assumption?” He says, “Well,
you voted for Obama. He’s a socialist, and therefore you
are.” And then I took it as if he had called me a dirty name.
And we got into an argument. And then after a while, he
said, “Well, I’m writing you off my list, Frank. Don’t ever
talk to me again. You’re no longer a friend of mine,” is how
that conversation ended. (Glass 2012)
The story of Frank and Ron may be common in
America, and, for many, it may be troubling. With the rise
of partisan polarization debated by academic and popular
commentators alike, many point to a link between diver-
gent political views and an incivility and breakdown of
political discourse. Dating back to the ancient Greeks,
721371PRQXXX10.1177/1065912917721371Political Research QuarterlyStrickler
research-article2017
1University of South Carolina, Columbia, USA
Corresponding Author:
Ryan Strickler, Department of Political Science, University of South
Carolina, 349 Gambrell Hall, Columbia, SC 29208-4114, USA.
Email: strickpr@email.sc.edu
Deliberate with the Enemy? Polarization,
Social Identity, and Attitudes toward
Disagreement
Ryan Strickler1
Abstract
As of late, political theory, research, and practice have taken a deliberative turn, extolling the benefits of idealized
public discourse. This paper explores how mass polarization impacts the preconditions for such discourse. Drawing
from social identity theory, partisanship is conceptualized as having distinct, yet interrelated social and ideological
dimensions. Through both online and telephone-based survey experiments, the paper then examines how these
two dimensions affect attitudes toward discussion that theorists prioritize. Strong social attachments to one’s party
consistently drive antideliberative attitudes toward disagreement; ideological partisan attachment, however, does
not have this effect. The results suggest that the rise of social identity polarization has driven the public away from
discursive norms that would support a deliberative democratic system.
Keywords
polarization, deliberative democracy, social identity, partisanship, public opinion
4 Political Research Quarterly 71(1)
political theorists have extolled the virtues of deliberative
democracy, predicated on the ability of political decision
makers to see divergent perspectives as legitimate and to
be open to opinion change (Dryzek 2010; Gutmann and
Thompson 1996; Rawls 1993). The closed-mindedness
and lack of consideration evinced by Frank and Ron calls
this possibility into question.
It is also perhaps puzzling, as many public opinion
scholars demonstrate that while conservatives and liber-
als may have increasingly sorted into their “correct” party
based on ideology, the public writ large is as moderate as
it has been in the past half-century (Fiorina 2011). The
acrimony may be real, but it is relatively untethered to
ideological or issue position conflict—in other words, “a
nation that agrees on many things but is bitterly divided
nonetheless” (Mason 2015, 128). To help explain this
puzzle, a body of recent research in political psychology
(Huddy, Mason, and Aarøe 2015; Iyengar, Sood, and
Lelkes 2012; Iyengar and Westwood 2015; Mason 2015,
2016) has drawn a distinction between the ideological
and social identity bases of partisanship to suggest that it
is not Democrats’ and Republicans’ political views, but
social identities, that are polarizing.
This paper demonstrates that the polarization of par-
tisan social identities is driving the public away from
deliberative discursive ideals. In particular, the focus is
on the concept of reciprocity (Gutmann and Thompson
1996), broadly defined as a good faith willingness to
give reasons and respond to disagreement in dialogue
with an open mind. Online and telephone survey experi-
ments show that those with strong social attachments to
their party are more likely to condition displays of reci-
procity on party cues rather than argumentative sub-
stance. Those with high partisan social identity salience
(“Social Partisans”) are both more likely to view inparty
disagreement with reciprocity as well as less likely to
view outparty disagreement with reciprocity, as com-
pared with those with lower social identity salience.
This partisan deliberative bias, however, is not consis-
tently present for those with stronger ideological attach-
ments to their party. These results highlight the negative
effect of mass social polarization on interparty dialogue
as well as deliberative decision making across the U.S.
political system.
Deliberative Democratic Systems
and Mass Discourse
Increasingly, democratic theory has taken a “deliberative
turn” (Dryzek 2010, 3), placing public discourse and
decision-making processes at the forefront of political
thought, empirical political inquiry, and real-world insti-
tutional development. Rather than focusing on elections
or rights, deliberative democratic theorists focus on
political communication and decision making. It is about
reason-giving (Thompson 2008); decisions are not made
by fiat, but with collective, interactive discussion, and
with justification toward those who disagree. Normative
theorists vary in their requirements for the quality of rea-
sons given, the role (if any) of power or bargaining, the
proper site for this discussion, as well as the primacy of
consensus as a discursive goal (Bächtiger et al. 2010). In
a seminal work, though, Gutmann and Thompson (1996)
argue that a key to ideal deliberation is a norm of reci-
procity. While this basic moral concept broadly means
that “we should return good for good, in proportion to
what we receive” (Becker 1986, 4), Gutmann and
Thompson (1996, 55) apply it to the realm of democratic
politics by stating that “when citizens deliberate, they
seek out agreement on substantive moral principles that
can be justified on the basis of mutually acceptable rea-
sons.” Recognizing the collective nature of democratic
decision making, political reasoning is given in terms that
those that disagree could, at least in theory, accept.
Consensus is sought, but in recognizing the reality of
moral disagreement (particularly in contemporary
American politics—see Jacoby 2014), reciprocity only
requires the honest effort to forge moral agreement, and
mutual respect for competing legitimate viewpoints when
consensus fails. While the term is Gutmann and
Thompson’s, the concept is nearly universally accepted
in deliberative literature, with roots in Habermas’s (1993)
theory of communicative rationality.
Scholarship on deliberation has traditionally focused
on discursive norms such as reciprocity for formal politi-
cal institutions. A reason for this is, for deliberative
democracy to matter, it cannot be just idle talk; delibera-
tive norms have to be consequential in government deci-
sion making. Many studies of deliberation, thus, have
focused on decision-making practices of legislative bod-
ies (Bächtiger et al. 2007) or specific empowered public
bodies such as juries (Sunstein 2002), advisory boards
(Warren and Gastil 2015), or deliberative polls (Fishkin
1995). This being said, theorists have increasingly broad-
ened their scope of inquiry and adopted a “systems”
approach (Mansbridge et al. 2012; Neblo 2015). In this
view, “deliberative democracy is more than a sum of
deliberative moments” (Mansbridge et al. 2012, 26); it is
rather a set of normative criteria that apply across a pol-
ity. For any component of a political system, the question
is not whether it is normatively ideal on its own but
whether it helps to foster policy making that is guided by
values such as high epistemic quality, mutual respect
across peoples and perspectives, and inclusive, impact
participation in political discourse. There is thus a divi-
sion of discursive labor, and components that may seem
ill-suited for deliberative democracy can potentially (but
not necessarily) serve a larger purpose.1

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT