Data-Driven Constitutional Avoidance

AuthorGregory P. Magarian, Lee Epstein, James L. Gibson
PositionProfessor of Law at Washington University in St. Louis/Ethan A.H. Shepley Distinguished University Professor at Washington University in St. Louis/Sidney W. Souers Professor of Government at Washington University in St. Louis
Pages1421-1453
1421
Data-Driven Constitutional Avoidance
Gregory P. Magarian, Lee Epstein & James L. Gibson*
ABSTRACT: This Article uses a case study to explain how empirical analysis
can promote judicial modesty. In Matal v. Tam, the U.S. Supreme Court
invoked the First Amendment to strike down the Lanham Act’s bar on federal
registration of “disparaging” trademarks. The Tam decision has great
constitutional significance. It expands First Amendment coverage into a new
field of economic regulation, and it deepens the constitutional prohibition on
viewpoint-based speech regulations. This Article contends that empirical
analysis could have given the Court a narrower basis for the Tam result, one
that would have avoided the fraught First Amendment issues the Court decided.
The Tam challenge came from an Asian-American rock band that calls itself
“The Slants”—as a means to reappropriate an anti-Asian slur. The authors
performed an original empirical study of how Americans understand the term
“slants.” The data show that both Asian-Americans and non-Asian-Americans
understand the term variably based on its context. Both groups recognize the
term’s derogatory meaning, but they also understand the use of the term by an
Asian-American band as an effort to reappropriate the derogatory term. This
contextual variation in how Americans understand the term “slants” exposes
the incoherence of the Lanham Act’s flat treatment of certain terms as uniformly
“disparaging.” That incoherence supports the legal conclusion that the
disparagement bar is unconstitutionally vague. A finding of vagueness in
Tam would have achieved relative constitutional avoidance, invalidating the
disparagement bar on a narrower, less constitutionally significant ground than
the actual decision’s First Amendment analysis. Constitutional avoidance
serves judicial modesty values that courts and our broader legal culture tend to
portray favorably. This Article’s study and analysis provide a model for other
situations in which empirical data can give courts a path to constitutional
avoidance.
*
Gregory P. Magarian is Professor of Law at Washington University in St. Louis; Lee Epstein is
the Ethan A.H. Shepley Distinguished University Professor at Washington University in St. Louis; and
James L. Gibson is the Sidney W. Souers Professor of Government at Washington University in St. Louis.
He is also a fellow at the Centre for Comparative and International Politics and Professor Extraordinary
in Political Science at (South Africa). We are deeply indebted to Steven S. Smith, Director of the
Weidenbaum Center at Washington University in St. Louis, for his support of this research, both for
allowing us to put our “Slants” module on The American Panel Survey and for funding an oversample
of people of Asian ancestry. We also appreciate the research assistance of Dan Sicorsky.
1422 IOWA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 104:1421
I.INTRODUCTION ........................................................................... 1422
II.THE FIRST AMENDMENT PRECIPICE OF MATAL V. TAM ................ 1424
A.THE CONSTITUTIONAL STAKES .............................................. 1425
1.Covering “Uncovered Speech” in the
Economic Realm ......................................................... 1425
2.Content and Viewpoint Discrimination .................... 1428
B.THE SUPREME COURTS TAM DECISION .................................. 1432
III.THE EMPIRICAL COMPLEXITY OF A “DISPARAGING TERM .......... 1436
IV.EMPIRICAL ANALYSIS AS A MEANS TO CONSTITUTIONAL
AVOIDANCE ................................................................................. 1440
A.INCOHERENCE, VAGUENESS, AND AVOIDANCE IN TAM .............. 1440
1.Incoherence as Vagueness .......................................... 1441
2.Vagueness as Avoidance .............................................. 1445
B.PROPAGATING DATA-DRIVEN AVOIDANCE ............................... 1447
V.CONCLUSION .............................................................................. 1452
APPENDIX .................................................................................... 1453
I. INTRODUCTION
Epitomizing Oliver Wendell Holmes’s truism “[g]reat cases like hard
cases make bad law”1 is the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in Matal v. Tam.2
Tam isn’t “great” because it involves especially momentous questions of public
policy. To the contrary: It centers on the quest of an obscure Asian-American
rock band to secure trademark protection for its name, “The Slants.” Rather,
Tam is a great case because, to quote Holmes, it “appeals to the feelings and
distorts the judgment.”3 The government refused to trademark the band’s
name on the theory that the term “slants” was insulting to Asian Americans
and therefore would violate a federal statutory bar on the registration of
“disparaging” trademarks (the “disparagement bar”).4 The government
ignored the band’s rationale for wanting the trademark: not to disparage
Asian Americans for their “slanted” eyes but to transform the slur into a badge
of pride—just as some gays, feminists, and blacks have attempted to
1. N. Sec. Co. v. United States, 193 U.S. 197, 400 (1904) (Holmes, J., dissenting).
2. See gener ally Matal v. Tam, 137 S. Ct. 1744 (2017) (holding that the disparagement
clause of the Lanham Act violated the Free Speech Clause of the First Amend ment).
3. N. Sec. Co., 193 U.S. at 400–01.
4. See infra notes 10–11 and accompanying text.
2019] DATA-DRIVEN CONSTITUTIONAL AVOIDANCE 1423
reappropriate5 derogatory labels (such as “queer, “bitch, and even the N-
word).6
If Tam is a “great case,” it also made “bad law. In striking down the
federal ban on disparaging trademarks, the Court invoked the most powerful
taboo in First Amendment speech law: the nearly absolute rule against
restricting speech because of its viewpoint.7 Taking t his step h ad the dual and
unnecessary effects of expanding the First Amendment’s scope to invalidate
a long-standing federal economic regulation and of broadening, by
elaboration, the rule against viewpoint-based discrimination.
We say “unnecessary” in the face of empirical evidence we developed in
an experiment focused on the Tam case. From the data, we learned that
Americans (Asians and non-Asians alike) construe the term “Slants”
differently depending on the context: They are more likely to believe a band’s
reappropriation motives when the band is Asian than when the band is not
Asian. Put another way, had The Slants been a white band, Americans would
have concluded that the band was out to disparage Asians, but Americans can
recognize when an Asian band deploys “Slants” to help Asians.
The natural conclusion from these data is that the bar on disparaging
trademarks simply lacked internal coherence. Had the Justices understood
this, they would have seen an alternative, less constitutionally momentous
ground for striking down the bar: vagueness. For two reasons, such a holding
would have transformed Tam from a “great case” exemplifying judicial
overreaching into a great decision promoting judicial modesty. First,
declaring the disparagement bar unconstitutionally vague would not have
pushed the boundaries of substantive First Amendment law into an uncharted
area of economic regulation. Second, grounding the decision in vagueness
would have eliminated the need to elaborate on the difficult concept of
viewpoint discrimination. A vagueness holding in Tam would have
exemplified constitutional avoidance: minimizing a decision’s constitutional
impact rather than making important new constitutional law.
These conclusions pertain to Tam, but the lessons of our study are larger.
Constitutional avoidance axiomatically serves to promote judicial modesty.
Conversely, courts’ forays into factual analysis often register as judicial
overreaching. Our Tam study complicates that dichotomy by showing how
5. By “reappropriate,” we refer to “the process of taking possession of a slur previously used
exclusively by dominant groups to reinforce a stigmatized group’s lesser status.” Adam D. Galinsky
et al., The Reappropriation of Stigmatizing Labels: The Reciprocal Relationship Between Power and S elf-
Labeling, 24 PSYCHOL. SCI. 2020, 2020 (2013).
6. See generally RANDALL KEN NEDY, NIGGER: THE STRANGE CAREER OF A TROUBLESOME WORD
(2002) (explaining the history of the N-word); Galinsky et al., supra note 5, at 2020 (noting that
study shows “self-labeling with a derogatory label can weaken the label’s stigmatizing force”);
Todd Anten, Note, Self-Disparaging Trademarks and Social Change: Factoring the Reappropriation of
Slurs into Section 2(A) of the Lanham Act, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 388 (2006) (analyzing trademarks
that include reappropriated racial slurs).
7. See infra notes 42–57 and accompanying text.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT