Contesting Counterpublics: The Transformation of the Articulation of Rural Migrant Workers’ Rights in China’s Public Sphere, 1992–2014

AuthorMujun Zhou
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/00323292211042441
Published date01 September 2022
Date01 September 2022
Subject MatterArticles
https://doi.org/10.1177/00323292211042441
Politics & Society
© The Author(s) 2021
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/00323292211042441
journals.sagepub.com/home/pas
Article
Contesting Counterpublics:
The Transformation of the
Articulation of Rural Migrant
Workers’ Rights in China’s
Public Sphere, 1992–2014
Mujun Zhou
Zhejiang University
Abstract
This article extends the theoretical discussion of counterpublics and applies the
concept to an authoritarian context. The article contends that it is necessary to
distinguish between the counterpublic oriented by liberal ideology that criticizes
authoritarianism at an abstract level (Counterpublic I) and the counterpublics that are
concerned with substantive inequality (Counterpublic II). To illustrate the approach
taken, the articulation of rural migrant workers’ rights between 1992 and 2014 is
documented, demonstrating that, in the 1990s and early 2000s, most public discussion
on the issue tended to reduce workers’ rights to civil rights. It was not until the late
2000s that alternative forms of rights, such as social rights, were thematized. As the
article argues, this was because the power balance between Counterpublic I and
Counterpublic II had been changed. The empirical study explains the transformation
and highlights the heterogeneity within Counterpublic II by comparing the diverse
strategies employed by different actors.
Keywords
public sphere, counterpublics, labor rights, civil society, China
Corresponding Author:
Mujun Zhou, Zhejiang University, 866 Yuhangtang Road, 1133 Innovation Building A, Hangzhou, Zhejiang
Province, 310058, China.
Email: Mujun_Zhou@protonmail.com
1042441PASXXX10.1177/00323292211042441Politics & SocietyZhou
research-article2021
2022, Vol. 50(3) 351–383
Since the 1990s, the development of information technology and the loosening of state
control in universities and the mass media have allowed for the flourishing of new
venues for public communication in China. In newly rising NGOs, commercialized
newspapers, and the internet space, people have criticized state policies and expressed
various demands. Many scholars, both in China and in the West, have seen these phe-
nomena as a sign of a rising public sphere.1 Most studies until now have focused on
how citizens have carved out space for participation vis-à-vis the authoritarian state.
However, few have considered the issue of power inequality within the sphere. Have
the newly rising venues privileged certain classes? To what extent are the disadvan-
taged groups able to make use of these venues to voice their concerns? Has the acces-
sibility of the public sphere changed over the past three decades?
The idea of the public sphere has come to the study of politics as a normative
theory.2 It portrays an ideal speech situation in which participants reach consensus
through rational-critical debates.3 In his early work, Jürgen Habermas locates the ori-
gin of the modern public sphere in the bourgeois society that existed between the late
Middle Ages and the eighteenth century. In his description, in the bourgeois conversa-
tions in salons, coffeehouses, and table societies during the transition from feudalism
to capitalism, a new norm was established—one in which economic power and the
prestige of public office were held in suspense and good arguments were deemed the
only legitimate means of persuasion. He contends that the bourgeois public sphere
performed the function of checking the absolutist state and that it laid a solid founda-
tion for the later expansion of democracy.4
Habermas’s interpretation has been widely criticized, both empirically and theoreti-
cally. Historical studies reveal that his analysis ignores the existence of various “plebe-
ian public spheres,” such as those organized by peasants and the working class. These
plebeian public spheres have developed alongside the bourgeois public sphere and
have been in conflictual relations with bourgeois publicity.5 Moreover, important parts
of the struggle to establish some of the features Habermas describes as integral to
bourgeois publicity, like freedom of the press, have largely been carried out by activ-
ists in those plebeian public spheres.6 From a different perspective, feminist theorists
hold that the bourgeois public sphere has never been as inclusive as it claims, as
women are for the most part excluded.7
In response to these criticisms, several scholars have argued for a notion of multiple
public spheres.8 Nancy Fraser’s discussion of subaltern counterpublics offers an illustra-
tive case. According to Fraser, subaltern counterpublics are those “parallel discursive
arenas” formulated by subordinated groups.9 These counterpublics have at least two
functions. On the one hand, by sheltering subordinated groups from the influence of the
public at large, subaltern counterpublics facilitate the circulation of counterdiscourses.
For example, in the conferences and local meetings organized by feminist activists in the
United States in the late twentieth century, women invented new terms, such as the “dou-
ble shift” and “sexual harassment,” to describe social reality. Armed with such language,
participants were able to recast their needs and identities.10 On the other hand, subaltern
counterpublics also assume a publicist orientation and are in the long run against separat-
ism. When the solidarity among the subordinated becomes strong and participants gain
352 Politics & Society 50(3)
confidence, counterpublics may serve as the basis for launching agitational activities.
Fraser thus contends that it is in the dialectic between withdrawal and agitation that sub-
altern counterpublics realize their emancipatory potential.11
While the idea of subaltern counterpublics provides us with an approach for under-
standing how disadvantaged groups can be included in the public sphere, the context
in which the conceptualization is based is rather parochial. Fraser’s discussion of
counterpublics has been limited to late capitalist societies, where the power of the state
is contained, and the freedom of speech and association is institutionally guaranteed
by formal democracy. In such a context, it is the power of privileged groups in society
(e.g., the white, male, propertied class) that subordinated groups intend to contest.
However, in an authoritarian context, the state monopolizes consensus formation, and
the freedom of speech and association is not guaranteed. It is arbitrary state repression
that participants in public discussions have to guard against. In this sense, in an author-
itarian regime, any communication networks that have been established for the sake of
questioning the state’s monopoly of politics—no matter whether they are established
by the privileged or the disadvantaged—can be seen as a kind of counterpublic.
What adds to the complexity of my analysis is that counterpublics in authoritarian
contexts can exist in many different forms. Some counterpublics tend to criticize
authoritarianism at a more abstract level, arguing that unchecked state power is essen-
tially bad. These counterpublics often claim to represent the general interest—as long
as the authoritarian control is dismantled, everyone will benefit. Other counterpublics
are more concerned with substantive inequality and injustice. These counterpublics
are often associated with socioeconomically disadvantaged groups in society. To dis-
tinguish between these two kinds of counterpublics, I will hereafter call them
Counterpublic I and Counterpublic II respectively.
I contend that the relationship between Counterpublic I and Counterpublic II is con-
tingent. In some cases, Counterpublic I and Counterpublic II merge. Notable examples
include workers’ resistance in Brazil, South Africa, and South Korea in the 1970s and
1980s. Such examples of resistance have not only criticized the exploitation of workers
in capitalist accumulation in late industrialized countries (Counterpublic II) but have
also evolved into movements that challenge authoritarian rule (Counterpublic I).12 But in
other cases, Counterpublic I and Counterpublic II can be separated. This can be due to
the fact that the major communicative venues of Counterpublic I are dominated by elites,
while ordinary people have little to no opportunity to participate. It can also be that,
although disadvantaged groups are formally incorporated into Counterpublic I, the inter-
nal structure of Counterpublic I is nonetheless highly hierarchical. In such a Counterpublic
I, although the disadvantaged can speak, their voices tend to be marginalized, and their
agenda is often labeled as of secondary importance. To address their concerns, the disad-
vantaged sometimes have to formulate an alternative communicative space
(Counterpublic II). When that happens, Counterpublic I and Counterpublic II may even
come into contestation with each other.
Central to my argument is that, when Counterpublic I and Counterpublic II do not
merge, it is necessary to consider the tripartite relations between Counterpublic I,
Counterpublic II, and the authoritarian state; whether the disadvantaged are able to
353
Zhou

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT