Confucianism, Moral Equality, and Human Rights: A Mencian Perspective

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/ajes.12084
Published date01 January 2015
Date01 January 2015
Confucianism, Moral Equality, and Human
Rights: A Mencian Perspective
By SUNGMOON KIM
ABSTRACT. This paper attempts to show the compatibility between
Confucianism and human rights, first by revisiting the moral philoso-
phy of Mencius, a key founder of the Confucian tradition, then by
reconstructing the Mencian-Confucian idea of human rights from
the perspective of his moral philosophy. One of my central claims is
that not only did Mencius acknowledge core human rights—
socioeconomic as well as civil-political—justified by his foundational
faith in universal moral equality and human dignity, but he further
understood the right to subsistence as an essential part of Confucian-
constitutional rights. Contrary to the widely received notion that in
Mencian-Confucianism the right to subsistence has an overriding value
vis-a-vis civil-political rights, I argue that Mencius (and Confucians in
general for that matter) never stipulated such a lexical ranking among
rights. I conclude by discussing how the type of Confucian moral
reasoning that Mencius employs in justifying the moral value of
human rights can be re-appropriated to produce Confucian rights
suitable for today.
..................
Introduction:
The Ongoing Debate Over Confucianism and Human Rights
In the past few decades, there have been a plethora of studies on the
compatibility between Confucianism and human rights. The purposes
of these studies vary. Some aim to rediscover and revivify Confucian-
ism’s humanist tradition, which in their view has been hijacked and
further exploited by authoritarian regimes in East Asia, as a cultural
resource for liberalism and democracy by making human rights an
integral part of modern Confucianism (de Bary 1983, 1998a; Tu 2002).
Others find this sort of attempt a poor representative of the authentic
American Journal of Economics and Sociology, Vol. 74, No. 1 (January, 2015).
DOI: 10.1111/ajes.12084
© 2015 American Journal of Economics and Sociology, Inc.
Confucian tradition, whose strong emphasis on human relationships
and particularized role ethics allows no room for the modern Western
conception of the free and autonomous self on which the rights
discourse is predicated (Rosemont 1988, 1991, 1998, 2004; Ames 1988,
2011; Hall and Ames 1987, 1999; Ihara 2004). Philosophical advocates
of the compatibility thesis take pains to differentiate Confucianism as
a tradition of philosophical thought from Confucianism as a political
ideology or actual state practices and attempt to reconstruct a modern
Confucianism that is fully compatible with the discourse and practice
of human rights (Chan 1999, 2014; Tiwald 2011). Still, skeptics of the
compatibility thesis, especially those who are keen on particular
economic and political contexts in which the East Asian governments
are situated, do not necessarily deny that Confucianism would
endorse a certain type of rights, particularly socioecomomic rights
such as a right to subsistence or a right to be fed, but they are
uncertain as to whether there is any room for civil-political rights in
the Confucian tradition; even if there is, they argue, the Confucian
tradition firmly establishes that socioeconomic rights have an overrid-
ing value via-a-vis civil-political rights (Bell 2006).
Though these studies have undoubtedly advanced our understand-
ing of Confucianism as well as whether or not Confucianism is
compatible with human rights (and if so, then, with what kind of
human rights in particular), there are two problems in existing studies.
First, participants in this compatibility debate tend to assume Confu-
cianism as a monolithic philosophical tradition, neglecting its varie-
gated sub-traditions with various philosophical doctrines, political
platforms, and policy orientations. As William de Bary (1998b) once
complained, scholars who draw attention to the humanist tradition in
traditional Confucianism often dismiss the important difference
between ancient Confucianism (created by the founders of the tradi-
tion such as Confucius, Mencius, and Xunzi) and Neo-Confucianism,
particularly of version advocated by Zhu Xi (1130–1200) and his
followers during the Song (960–1279) and Ming (1368–1644) dynasties
in China and the Choso˘n dynasty (1392–1910) in Korea, which gave
rise to what some scholars call “constitutional culture” in the Confu-
cian political tradition (Chu 1998; Hahm 2009). I propose that even
among the three ancient Confucian masters there are still meaningful
150 The American Journal of Economics and Sociology
differences as to whether there is room for the notion of human rights
in their respective philosophical thought, given their different concep-
tions of human nature (Ivanhoe 2000; Van Norden 2000), different
ideas of the origin of the civil state, and, albeit arguably, different
conceptualizations of the constitutional polity (Kim 2011). Since Con-
fucianism as a philosophical tradition never constituted its political
theory in terms of human rights, it is crucial to refrain from attributing
a (seminal) notion of rights to the tradition in general, even if we find
what may seem like “rights” in an individual thinker’s philosophical
thought, especially when dealing with ancient Confucians, to whom
both compatibilists and incompatibilists turn in order to make their
cases.
Second and relatedly, when we are relating the notion of human
rights to the Confucian tradition, we should be clear about in what
intellectual context we are introducing the notion—are we engaging
primarily in an interpretive task (i.e., to discover the notion of
rights, or its equivalent, in Confucian philosophical thought) or are
we trying to advocate human rights in modern East Asian countries
that have a Confucian heritage, to which the concept (especially the
philosophical concept of rights) has been completely unknown until
the late 19th century (Angle 2002)? In the existing literature, these
otherwise distinct philosophical tasks (i.e., interpretive or normative)
are often conflated, inviting many questions, theoretical as well as
practical. For instance, noting the virtual absence of the concept of
rights in core Confucian classics, some incompatibilists boldly assert
that, in contemporary China, the notion of rights is completely irrel-
evant. But why should the observation that ancient Confucianism
was not constituted around the idea of rights lead to the complete
denial of the significance of human rights in modern China, where
citizens are now fully aware of the crucial importance of a variety
of rights?1
Compatibilists have their own problems when they claim that
Confucian rights discovered in classical texts comprehensively define
contemporary life in East Asian, historically Confucian, societies. This
is a problematic presumption because even though, evidently, East
Asians are saturated with Confucian habits and mores, they are not
Confucians in a philosophically monist and culturally monolithic
Confucianism, Moral Equality, and Human Rights 151

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT