Conflicts of Values and Political Forgiveness

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/puar.12214
Published date01 May 2014
Date01 May 2014
Paul Nieuwenburg is associate
professor of political philosophy in the
Department of Political Science at Leiden
University and codirector of the Centre of
Political Philosophy. He has held positions
in departments of philosophy, public
administration, and legal philosophy as
well. His research focuses on issues in moral
psychology, public ethics, and constitutional
theory. He is interested in both historical
and systematic aspects of political philoso-
phy and tries to combine these interests
where possible.
E-mail: pnieuwenburg@fsw.leidenuniv.nl
374 Public Administration Review • May | June 2014
Public Administration Review,
Vol. 74, Iss. 3, pp. 374–382. © 2014 by
The American Society for Public Administration.
DOI: 10.1111/puar.12214.
Paul Nieuwenburg
Leiden University, The Netherlands
Citizens have a right to be governed by of‌f‌i cials with
an acute awareness of the conf‌l icts between the consti-
tutional values of liberal democracy. Such an awareness
is an integral part of a public of‌f‌i cial’s integrity.  at is
why citizens should have a say in deciding whether to
remove from of‌f‌i ce an of‌f‌i cial with such integrity. In this
article, this type of conf‌l ict between constitutional values
is translated into the terms of an individual of‌f‌i cial’s
decision making with the help of moral theory.  is yields
two paradoxes: one focusing on the decision maker and
the other on the object of his or her decisions: the citizen.
ese paradoxes lead to the following questions: If run-
ning a liberal democratic constitution essentially involves
moral complexity, should we not try to have it run by of‌f‌i -
cials with a sensitivity to that complexity? And if of‌f‌i cials
with that sensitivity are bound to commit moral wrongs
because of complexity, do not we owe them something like
political forgiveness?  e paradoxes are used to formulate
conditions for political forgiveness.
While the integrity of a public of‌f‌i cial is mul-
tifaceted and complex, it certainly includes
the endorsement of values enshrined in
the constitution that, in the words of the late John
Rohr (1986), he or she has to “run.” But what if these
values clash violently in a moral dilemma? Such is
the predicament of the police of‌f‌i cer in the following
real-life case.
On September 27, 2002, Jakob von Metzler, son
of a Frankfurt-based private banker, is kidnapped
by 27-year-old law student Magnus Gäfgen. In a
letter to Jakob’s parents, Gäfgen demands a ransom
of 1 million euros. Two days later, the kidnapper is
identif‌i ed while collecting the money.  e next day,
on September 30, Gäfgen is arrested by the Frankfurt
police. During interrogation, Gäfgen consistently
misinforms his interrogators as to the whereabouts of
Jakob. At one point, Gäfgen tells them to go and take
a look at a cottage near a lake not far from Frankfurt.
In the cottage, police of‌f‌i cers f‌i nd a bed with blood-
stained blankets.  ey surmise that if Jakob is still
alive, he is likely to be in serious danger.
In the early morning hours of October 1, 2002, all
this is reported to the responsible of‌f‌i cer, Wolfgang
Daschner, vice president of the Frankfurt police. After
20 minutes of agonizing deliberation, Daschner orders
Gäfgen’s interrogators to threaten him with what is
in ef‌f ect a (relatively mild) form of torture. When the
latter is confronted with the threat, he at once gives
way. Gäfgen reveals that Jakob is no longer alive. On
October 14, he gives a full confession. More than
half a year later, on July 27, 2003, he is convicted for
abduction and homicide. He is sent to prison for the
rest of his life.
Having issued the order, Daschner informs the
Staatsanwalt, or public prosecutor.  e public pros-
ecutor, who, according to German penal law, has no
discretionary authority to decide whether or not to
prosecute, has no choice but to start an investigation.
Meanwhile, Daschner is demoted as a result of an
internal disciplinary measure. His new task consists
of performing menial administrative chores, awaiting
his case to be examined in court. On February 20,
2004, Daschner is indicted, and in December of that
year, he is convicted.  e sentence is mild: he gets
a conditional f‌i ne (Verwarnung mit Strafvorbehalt)
of 10,800 euros.  e relevant article of the German
penal code (§ 59 Strafgezetzbuch), which is seldom
applied, makes it possible to punish someone formally
without punishing him materially.  e newspapers
aptly comment that Daschner has been convicted
but not punished.  e case again receives a lot of
exposure in the German media in 2011. In August of
that year, Gäfgen successfully seeks compensation for
having been threatened with torture by the authori-
ties: the state has to pay him 3,000 euros (Frankfurter
Allgemeine Zeitung, October 10, 2012). A wave of
public moral indignation washes over Germany.
e reputable German weekly Die Zeit comments,
“Rechtens, aber nicht richtig” (Legal, but not right)
(Die Zeit, August 4, 2011).
Cases of this kind should make a citizen of any liberal
democracy think—and think hard. Such a case brings
Conf‌l icts of Values and Political Forgiveness

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT