Conflict and Universal Moral Theory

Date01 October 2007
DOI10.1177/0090591707304587
Published date01 October 2007
AuthorEva Erman
Subject MatterArticles
598
Political Theory
Volume 35 Number 5
October 2007 598-623
© 2007 Sage Publications
10.1177/0090591707304587
http://ptx.sagepub.com
hosted at
http://online.sagepub.com
Author’s Note: Special thanks go to James Gordon Finlayson, Jens Bartelson, and Niklas
Möller for constructive comments. I also wish to thank Jeremy Waldron; the political theory
workshop at Columbia University; the Stockholm political theory group, in particular Sofia
Näsström; as well as the participants of the 3rd International Conference on Political Theory
in Roskilde, Denmark (March 1–2, 2006). Finally, I am grateful to the Swedish Research
Council for financing my research project on human rights, deliberation, and conflict resolu-
tion, and to the two anonymous referees of Political Theory.
Conflict and Universal
Moral Theory
From Reasonableness to Reason-Giving
Eva Erman
Stockholm University, Sweden
The solutions to moral problems offered by contemporary moral theories
largely depend on how they understand pluralism. This article compares two
different kinds of universal moral theories, liberal impartiality theory and
discourse ethics. It defends the twofold thesis that (1) a dialogical theory
such as discourse ethics is better equipped to give an account of pluralism
than impartiality theory due to a more correct understanding of the nature of
conflict, but that (2) discourse ethics cannot, contrary to what Jürgen
Habermas claims, embrace the notion of impartiality connected to agent-
neutrality. The article argues that pluralism reflects conflicts among values
not only between but also within people and that discourse ethics can include
both these dimensions since it recognizes the constitutive connection
between deliberation and (moral) conflict. Thus, unlike impartiality theory, it
can elucidate the transformative aspects of pluralism.
Keywords: impartiality theory; moral conflict; discourse ethics; Habermas;
deliberation
Introduction
The solutions to moral problems offered by contemporary moral theories
largely depend on how they understand pluralism. This article com-
pares two different kinds of universal moral theories, liberal impartiality
theory and discourse ethics. It is claimed that impartiality theory in general
Erman / Conflict and Universal Moral Theory 599
has difficulty in giving a satisfactory account of pluralism, since the “fact of
pluralism” is rigidly interpreted as a static rather than dynamic state of
affairs. The twofold thesis I defend is that (1) a dialogical theory such as dis-
course ethics is better equipped to give an account of pluralism than impar-
tiality theory due to a more correct understanding of the nature of conflict,
but that (2) discourse ethics cannot, contrary to what Jürgen Habermas
claims, embrace a notion of impartiality connected to agent-neutrality. It
is argued that, by understanding conflict as a dialogical phenomenon,
discourse ethics can elucidate the transformative aspects of pluralism.
The structure of the argument is as follows: in their effort to theorize
about moral norms, impartialists such as Brian Barry, Thomas Nagel, and
Charles Larmore connect the notion of impartiality to neutrality and rea-
sonableness through a hypothetical procedure (I). By doing so they presup-
pose two things: firstly, that certain conflicting notions of the good are
already in place, towards which we must be impartial. A hypothetical pro-
cedure assumes that a standard is already at our disposal, in this case pro-
viding independent criteria for recognizing whether impartiality towards
conflicting conceptions of the good has been achieved by the impartial pro-
cedure.1However, I argue that impartiality means to be im-partial towards
something and that conflicts are not simply there; they emerge in interac-
tion, in the meeting between (at least) two subjects. Secondly, impartialists
presume that conflicts are to be understood in interpersonal terms and that
pluralism consists of conflicting unitary comprehensive doctrines. But is
this depiction of modern pluralist societies appropriate? I don’t think so. In
modern societies very few people have unified comprehensive doctrines.
Pluralism reflects conflicts among values not only between people but also
within them. The reason why a dialogical theory can offer a more accurate
understanding of the nature of conflict is because it can include these
dimensions. It takes the step from reasonableness to reason-giving and
thereby recognizes that deliberation is constitutive of moral conflict.
Deliberation is an exercise of autonomous agency, of self-determination, as
well as a cognitive exercise, of self-interpretation. It involves both an inter-
personal and an intrapersonal dimension, which means that conflicts occur
not only between persons but also within them. Moreover, the two dimen-
sions are interdependent since in our deliberation and conflicts with others
we search coherence among our own conflicting values, which has an
impact on how we view others as well as our differences. The article thus
argues that conflict is of cognitive value and that a dialogical understand-
ing of conflict can give a more satisfactory account of the dynamic aspects
of pluralism (II).2

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT