Beyond Stork Delivery: From Injury to Autonomy in Reconceptualising ‘Harm’ in Wrongful Pregnancy

Published date27 March 2006
DOIhttps://doi.org/10.1016/S1059-4337(05)38004-5
Pages105-149
Date27 March 2006
AuthorNicolette M. Priaulx
BEYOND STORK DELIVERY: FROM
INJURY TO AUTONOMY IN
RECONCEPTUALISING ‘HARM’ IN
WRONGFUL PREGNANCY
Nicolette M. Priaulx
ABSTRACT
Can one describe the ‘natural’ process of pregnancy as ‘harm’, even when
negligently brought about? What does that harm consist of? Offering a
contextual analysis of the English judiciary’s characterisation of wrongful
pregnancy, this paper demonstrates from a feminist perspective that the
current construction of pregnancy as a ‘personal injury’ is deeply prob-
lematic. Forwarding an alternative account, this paper argues for law to
embrace a richer notion of autonomy that will better resonate with wom-
en’s diverse experiences of reproduction, and articulate the importance of
autonomy in the reproductive domain: notably, women gaining control
over their moral, relational and social lives.
Studies in Law, Politics, and Society, Volume 38, 105–149
Copyright r2006 by Elsevier Ltd.
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 1059-4337/doi:10.1016/S1059-4337(05)38004-5
105
INTRODUCTION
She pondered. ‘‘Androids can’t bear children,’’ she said, then. ‘‘Is that a loss?’’
He finished undressing her. Exposed her pale, cold loins.
‘‘Is it a loss?’’ Rachel repeated. ‘‘I don’t really know; I have no way to tell. How does it
feel to have a child? How does it feel to be born, for that matter? We’re not born; we
don’t grow up; instead of dying from illness or old age we wear out like ants. Ants again;
that’s what we are. Not you; I mean me. Chitinous reflex-machines who aren’t really
alive.’’ (Dick, 1968, p. 165).
Pregnancy is woman’s work (Murphy, 1989). It is the one experience that
‘inevitably differentiates women from men’ and thus forms a ‘crucial part of
our identity which we cannot ignore, even supposing we would wish to do
so’ (Atkins & Hoggett, 1984, p. 83). The fact that most women hold the
capacity to bear children, Anne Morris and Susan Nott (1995) reflect has
had adverse consequences for the treatment of women in society. The dom-
inant ideology of reproduction positions and defines women in terms of
their potential mothering role (Morell, 2000) and thereby exercises a reg-
ulatory role over all women’s lives. Nor has the increasing incidence of
infertility and deliberate childlessness displaced this view. Childless life is
not perceived as being a ‘viable or appealing choice’ and ‘women who pur-
posefully do not have children are not taken on their own terms, but are
measured by the idealised standard of motherhood’ (Morell, 2000, p. 314).
Whilst pro-natalist norms hold a powerful influence on the way that women
are viewed, non-pregnant women are nevertheless assumed to have the ca-
pacity to make valid self-determining choices about their lives and destinies,
in a way that the pregnant women rarely are. The pregnant woman’s body is
no longer her own, it labours now for another – she is not one person ‘but
two – mother and foetus – and society may expect, even demand that her
freedom is curtailed in the interests of the foetus’ (Morris & Nott, 1995, p.
54–55). Under an ideology whereby ‘the foetus is something to be protected
from its mother’ (Diduck, 1993, p. 471), the rational and sane mother must
willingly accept treatment by medical professionals, for ‘no normal mother-
to-be’ would persist with a course that would cause serious harm to her
foetus. As a result, pregnant women are confronted with a law that speaks
‘loudly of care and protection of children, and less loudly but perhaps more
profoundly, of control of women’ (Diduck, 1993, p. 465).
It is in this context that this paper explores wrongful pregnancy in the
tort of negligence in the United Kingdom. This becomes important when
considering that the law has been more involved in conceptualising women
NICOLETTE M. PRIAULX106
as a ‘‘harm’’ to foetal health, than as harmed through the experience of
pregnancy itself. Therefore, while society values motherhood for its product,
a healthy child, and is one which construes motherhood as naturally in-
volving sacrifice, the law rarely speaks the language of the care and pro-
tection of the rights, health and integrity of pregnant women. But in
confronting the action of wrongful pregnancy, this is the language de-
manded of it. Does wrongful pregnancy constitute a personal injury or
merely a harmless biological function that cannot constitute ‘‘damage’’ or
‘‘harm’’? The significance of this question lies at the heart of the tort of
negligence.
A number of torts, such as trespass or libel, are actionable per se – with-
out evidence of damage.
1
The absence of damage is not germane to such
actions since tort law operates here to ‘vindicate private rights and not
necessarily to compensate the victim’ (Markesinis & Deakin, 1999, p. 18).
By contrast, in the law of negligence, ‘‘damage’’ holds a central role and is
said to form the ‘gist of the action’ (Stapleton, 1988, p. 213). Therefore, a
claimant will not only need to establish a duty of care, a breach of that duty,
and that the breach caused the damage complained of – she must also show
that the type of harm she has suffered is one that is accepted by the law as
‘actionable’. This proves unproblematic in the case of the ‘straightforward
results of many physical acts of negligence’ (Atiyah, 1997, p. 52). Beyond the
broken bones and personal injuries obvious to the human eye, it is well
recognised that ‘damage can be recovered for any physical harm’ (Atiyah,
1997, p. 53). Therefore, gastroenteritis suffered through swallowing parts of
a snail in a bottle of ginger beer, cancer or lung diseases suffered through
exposure to asbestos in the workplace, will most certainly constitute phys-
ical harms for the purposes of negligence (Witting, 2002). The question is, in
what way might an unwanted pregnancy – a normal, biological function,
although unwanted, be conceptualised as actionable physical damage for the
purposes of negligence? It is undeniable that there are salient differences
between an unwanted pregnancy and broken bones, but what do they con-
sist of? What is a ‘personal injury’, and importantly, who defines it? Does it
matter for these purposes that while some pregnancies are unwanted, others
are not? Or in determining this issue should we merely be content with the
weaker view that pregnancy should be treated as analogous to a personal
injury, so as to avoid the difficult arguments that pregnancy gives rise to
(Mullis, 1993)? And indeed, if wrongful pregnancy does constitute ‘‘dam-
age’’ what rights/interests are being implicated and how do such concep-
tualisations of harm intersect or conflict with alternative representations of
the processes of pregnancy and childbirth? As Morris and Nott (1995)
Reconceptualising ‘Harm’ in Wrongful Pregnancy 107

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT