Beyond the pro-consumption tax consensus.

AuthorShaviro, Daniel N.

INTRODUCTION I. THE OPTIMAL INCOME TAX FRAMEWORK A. Optimal Income Taxation and the Underlying Information Problem B. Taxation and Inequality C. Taxing Earnings in a Welfarist Framework D. Extensions of the Optimal Income Tax Framework E. Atkinson-Stiglitz and the Case for a Uniform Commodity Tax II. THE CASE FOR (AND AGAINST) INCOME AVERAGING A. Annual Versus Lifetime Systems B. The Permanent Income Hypothesis C. The Case for Income Averaging Under the Permanent Income Hypothesis 1. Distribution 2. Efficiency D. Implementing Income Averaging E. Problems with the Case for Income Averaging 1. Incomplete markets a. "Great expectations" b. Risk c. Inability to annuitize 2. Departures from consistent rational choice a. Hyperbolic discounting and other causes of myopia b. Mental accounts 3. Additional information a. Past earnings b. Savings c. Age-related wage distribution and labor supply elasticity F. Conclusions Regarding Income Averaging III. IMPLICATIONS FOR THE CHOICE BETWEEN INCOME AND CONSUMPTION TAXATION A. Overlap Between the Cases for Income Averaging and for Consumption Taxation B. The Distributional Case for Consumption Taxation Under the Permanent Income Hypothesis C. The Efficiency Case for Consumption Taxation Under the Permanent Income Hypothesis D. Problems with the Case for Consumption Taxation 1. Incomplete markets 2. Departures from consistent rational choice 3. Additional information E. Conclusions Regarding Consumption Taxation CONCLUSION INTRODUCTION

For many decades in United States tax policy debate, fundamental tax reform was identified primarily with adopting a comprehensive income tax base. (1) In the last ten or so years, it has increasingly come to denote instead replacing the income tax with a consumption tax. (2) This shift has been as unmistakable in the academic literature as in public political debate. (3) Its occurrence is important, even though in my view the prospects for fundamental reform are decidedly dim, (4) because ideas and ideals matter.

In academic circles, the shift reflects an emerging new consensus (widespread if not universal) that an ideal consumption tax is unambiguously superior to an ideal income tax, (5) taking into account concerns of both efficiency and distribution. This view rejects any tradeoff between the two types of ideal tax bases, such as between greater progressivity and greater efficiency, (6) or between different kinds of efficiency. (7) Rather, the ideal consumption tax is viewed as capable of being equally progressive but more efficient, or equally efficient but more progressive, causing it to dominate the ideal income tax in any comparison. (8)

There is something mystifying about this shift in ideals, no matter how intellectually persuasive one finds it. Consider a second possible shift in normative framework, from favoring an annual income or consumption tax to favoring one that is lifetime-based. Under a lifetime-based system, even if tax payments are remitted annually, lifetime rather than merely annual economic results determine how much one must pay. Thus, people with fluctuating incomes do not end up paying more tax than those with stable incomes, as happens under an annual system with graduated marginal rates. A lifetime-based system that still employs annual tax returns can be implemented through income averaging, a system that the economist William Vickrey proposed nearly seventy years ago (9) and that the U.S. federal income tax featured in a much more limited fashion from 1964 through 1986. (10) Income averaging has received extensive, but on the whole surprisingly unfavorable, attention in the tax policy literature, (11) even though the intellectual case for it substantially overlaps with that underlying the new pro-consumption tax consensus. At the level of ideals, leaving aside differences in administrative feasibility, it makes little sense to accept one idea while viewing the other so skeptically.

The reason for the overlap is that the case for a consumption tax, no less than that for income averaging, relies on taking a lifetime, rather than a current-year or snapshot, perspective in evaluating individuals' welfare and in predicting their behavior. A simple example can help to demonstrate this intuitively. Suppose that, in a given year, Xavier and Yolanda each spend their entire $100,000 salaries on consumption, and thus are treated the same by a consumption tax even though Xavier has a million dollars in the bank while Yolanda has no savings. How can this be justified, when Xavier is obviously so much better-off? The answer, from a consumption tax standpoint, is that Xavier does indeed bear a much higher tax burden, because in the long run he will be taxed just as heavily, as if he had spent the million dollars, on top of the $100,000, this year. (12) This argument, however, requires taking a lifetime rather than a merely annual perspective--and indeed, perhaps, a longer than single-life perspective if Xavier leaves money to his heirs--raising, as we will see, the very same issues as the case for income averaging.

The persistence of the peculiar disjuncture between the income versus consumption tax debate and the income averaging debate reflects under-appreciation both of the affirmative case for income averaging and of its relationship to the case for a consumption tax. In addition, while consumption taxation certainly does not lack critics, its reliance on the same long-term perspective as income averaging remains under-appreciated. However, this reliance on a long-term perspective makes the cases both for income averaging and for consumption taxation depend on the accuracy of the assumptions needed to support the use of such a perspective. In particular, such reliance rests on three critical assumptions, each of which is subject to challenge.

1) Complete markets. Markets are complete when they cover every possible commodity and combination thereof. (13) In illustration, with complete labor markets one can work at one's wage rate for any number of hours between zero and full-time. (14) With complete capital markets, one can hold financial positions that would pay off in every possible state of the world, thus providing effective insurance against any possible contingency. (15) Complete markets are necessary to the full achievement of allocative efficiency in the economy. (16) In the income averaging and income versus consumption tax debates, their absence would mean that people with the same lifetime resources might actually face very different circumstances in each period, suggesting that they should not necessarily pay the same lifetime taxes.

2) Consistent rational choice. Under conventional economic assumptions, people have stable preferences that determine the utility they will experience in alternative states of the world and that they consult to make decisions aimed at maximizing expected utility. (17) People therefore are assumed to engage in consistent rational choice, suggesting that they will make the same choice from within a given opportunity set no matter how the choices are presented or framed. Weakening this assumption, by positing that people are myopic, for example, can undermine the cases for income averaging and consumption taxation by suggesting that behavior and well-being may significantly depend on current period resources, rather than simply on the lifetime total.

3) Within-period information. A final assumption underlying use of the long-term perspective to support income averaging and consumption taxation relates to achieving the tax system's distributional objectives, rather than to the choice of analytic timeframe as such. Specifically, this assumption holds that, once one has picked the relevant period for evaluating how well-off people are (such as by measuring their income or consumption for the period), information about when within the period the taxpayer acted or benefited does not provide further useful guidance for distribution policy. Thus, in an annual system, people who earn or spend a lot in January typically are treated the same as those who ended the year in the same overall position but followed a different sequence (such as earning or spending more evenly across time, or with back-loading instead of front-loading). With a lifetime perspective, this assumption becomes more controversial. The gap between, say, the ages of 21 and 75 is much bigger than that between January and December of a single year. An individual may change much more during such an extended period, and the tax system may have much more to gain informationally from looking within the period, rather than just at total results for the period as a whole. This undermines the case for income averaging and consumption taxation by suggesting that the particular sequence of the taxpayer's earnings and/or consumption, not just the taxpayer's lifetime income, should affect how she is treated both overall and at different times within her lifespan.

In this Article, I will show that none of the three assumptions that are needed to make an overwhelming case for income averaging and consumption taxation fully holds. Incomplete markets and departures from consistent rational choice can make current-period information about an individual's circumstances relatively more important than consumption taxation and income averaging effectively recognize. The effect, however, is more to muddy the analysis than affirmatively to support income taxation or a predominantly annual system.

Problems with the third assumption, pertaining to within-period information, potentially have stronger implications. As we will see, the relevance of the within-period components of lifetime information can affirmatively support taxing saving, in keeping with an income tax but not a consumption tax. In addition, in some circumstances there may be grounds for imposing higher taxes on people with declining earnings than on those with level...

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT