Beliefs and Public Good Provision with Anonymous Contributors

Date01 October 2016
AuthorJOSE A. RODRIGUES‐NETO,WILFREDO LEIVA MALDONADO
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jpet.12161
Published date01 October 2016
BELIEFS AND PUBLIC GOOD PROVISION WITH ANONYMOUS
CONTRIBUTORS
WILFREDO LEIVA MALDONADO
Catholic University of Bras´
ılia
JOSE A. RODRIGUES-NETO
Australian National University
Abstract
We analyze a static game of public good contributions where finitely
many anonymous players have heterogeneous preferences about the
public good and heterogeneous beliefs about the distribution of pref-
erences. In the unique symmetric equilibrium, the only individuals who
make positive contributions are those who most value the public good
and who are also the most pessimistic; that is, according to their beliefs,
the proportion of players who most like the public good is smaller than
it would be according to any other possible belief. We predict whether
the aggregate contribution is larger or smaller than it would be in an
analogous game with complete information and heterogeneous prefer-
ences, by comparing the beliefs of contributors with the true distribu-
tion of preferences. A trade-off between preferences and beliefs arises
if there is no individual who simultaneously has the highest preference
type and the most pessimistic belief. In this case, there is a symmetric
equilibrium, and multiple symmetric equilibria occur only if there are
more than two preference types.
1. Introduction
Paul Samuelson pioneered the analysis of public goods provision.1More recent litera-
ture on the provision of public goods under incomplete information usually assumes
that incompleteness arises from either ignorance about players’ preferences, for in-
stance Bac(1996), Menezes, Monteiro, and Temimi (2001), and Bag and Roy (2008),
1See Samuelson (1954, 1955), as well as Olson (1965).
Wilfredo Leiva Maldonado, Catholic University of Braslia, Brazil (wilfredo@pos.ucb.br). Jose A.
Rodrigues-Neto, Australian National University, Canberra, Australia (jarnwi@yahoo.com).
Wilfredo Leiva Maldonado acknowledges the financial support of CNPq (Brazil) through Grant
303420/2012-0. We would like to thank James Taylor and seminar participants at the Australian Na-
tional University for comments, and Merrilyn L´
arusson for the English editing. We would also like to
thank three excellent reviewers for their many corrections and suggestions. All remaining errors are
our own responsibility.
Received February 20, 2015; Accepted March 3, 2015.
C2016 Wiley Periodicals, Inc.
Journal of Public Economic Theory, 18 (5), 2016, pp. 691–708.
691
692 Journal of Public Economic Theory
or from ignorance about peers’ wealth, as in Andreoni (1988), Gradstein (1992), and
Gradstein, Nitzan, and Slutsky (1994). However, in some situations in practice, it is un-
likely that each individual knows the identity of all her peers. Even when each player
knows the identities of all players, we may not wish to assume that each player is capa-
ble of forming a joint distribution about the profiles of types of other players. It seems
more reasonable that each player simply has her own perception of the distribution of
relevant characteristics of the population.
Hellwig (2011) introduces a general mathematical framework to work with incom-
plete information games in a large population of anonymous players.2This is a con-
venient modeling setup in games where the relevant variable for a player is only the
aggregate action of the others. Examples of this framework are voting games, Cournot
competition and public contribution games.
Our work analyzes a static game of individual contributions to a continuous public
good by a finite population of heterogeneous anonymous players. The heterogeneity
comes from two sources: (1) the preferences for, or values of, the public good—what
we refer to as the player’s type or preference type; and (2) the beliefs about the distri-
bution of types among the population. Unlike most of the literature, we do not assume
that each player knows the correct joint distribution of her peers’ (preference) types.
Instead, each player has a belief about how the population is divided by types. Each
individual has quasi-linear utility in her private good consumption and chooses how
much of her initial endowment to consume or to give to the pool of contributions to
the public good.
In this setup, we prove that there is always a symmetric equilibrium; that is, a Nash
equilibrium where all players with the same characteristic (same type and belief) make
identical contributions. In such a symmetric equilibrium, only players with the highest
preference type and the most pessimistic belief (i.e., the one with the lowest proportion
of the highest type players) make positive contributions, provided that there is at least
one such player. In this situation, the total contribution to the public good could be
greater, smaller, or equal to the total contribution under an analogous game of com-
plete information with heterogeneous preferences. It is greater if and only if the players
that actually contribute are pessimistic relative to the true distribution of preferences,
which means that they believe that the number of the highest type players is smaller
than it actually is. This result allows us to evaluate how the classical free-rider problem
depends on the heterogeneity of beliefs and on the preferences present in the popula-
tion. If there are many possible types and players, and only few of them have the most
pessimistic belief, then the free-rider problem is severe. This is because only a relatively
small minority of players contributes and these contributions are relatively large. More-
over, contributors may be better off than noncontributors of different types. This is true
because contributors benefit more from the same amount of public good than players
with a different preference type.
If there is no individual who simultaneously has the highest preference type and
the most pessimistic belief, a compensatory interaction between preferences and be-
liefs arises. Depending on the parameters, there may be symmetric equilibria where all
2As Hellwig (2011) explains, “This formulation of incomplete information departs from the personal-
istic approach where each agent is assumed to receive a signal about the underlying state of the world
and uses the signal to form probabilistic beliefs about the state of the world, about the signals received
by the other agents and about the other agents’ beliefs that are induced by their signals . .. here, agents
do not form beliefs about any particular other agents. They only form beliefs about the cross-section
distribution of the other agents’ characteristics.”

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT