Behavioral insurance and economic theory: A literature review

AuthorJia Min Ng,Glenn W. Harrison
Published date01 July 2019
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/rmir.12119
Date01 July 2019
© 2019 The American Risk and Insurance Association
Risk Manag Insur Rev. 2019;22:133182. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/rmir
|
133
Received: 1 May 2019
|
Accepted: 1 May 2019
DOI: 10.1111/rmir.12119
INVITED ARTICLE
Behavioral insurance and economic theory:
A literature review
Glenn W. Harrison
1,3
|
Jia Min Ng
2
1
Department of Risk Management &
Insurance and Center for the Economic
Analysis of Risk, Robinson College of
Business, Georgia State University,
Atlanta, Georgia
2
Center for the Economic Analysis of
Risk, Robinson College of Business,
Georgia State University, Atlanta,
Georgia
3
School of Economics, University of Cape
Town, Cape Town, South Africa
Correspondence
Glenn W. Harrison, Department of Risk
Management & Insurance and Center for
the Economic Analysis of Risk, Robinson
College of Business, Georgia State
University, Atlanta, Georgia.
Email: gharrison@gsu.edu
Jia Min Ng, Center for the Economic
Analysis of Risk, Robinson College of
Business, Georgia State University,
Atlanta, Georgia.
Email: jiamin.ng@outlook.com
Abstract
Decisions to purchase insurance should be a perfect
place to see economic theory at work in general, and
behavioral economics at work in particular. We have
welldeveloped theories of the demand for, and welfare
evaluation of, insurance products. These theories extend
relatively easily to the insights of behavioral economics.
Unfortunately, the empirical literature has not main-
tained this tight connection. In fact, much of the
empirical literature illustrates the dangers of the modern
passion with agnostic economics: avoiding theory at all
costs to focus on what works.We identify these
dangers and the implications in the literature.
1
|
INTRODUCTION
Decisions to purchase insurance should be a perfect place to see economic theory at work
in general, and behavioral economics at work in particular. We have welldeveloped
theories of the demand for, and welfare evaluation of, insurance products. These theories
extend relatively easily to the insights of behavioral economics.
1
Unfortunately, the
empirical literature has not maintained this tight connection with theory. In fact, much of
the empirical literature illustrates the dangers of the modern passion with agnostic
------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
1
Behavioral economics is not defined here, nor should it be, as just the study of anomalies or irrationality.
economics: avoiding theory at all costs to focus on what works.We identify these
dangers and the implications for the behavioral insurance literature.
2
To keep the focus tight we limit discussions to empirical studies that use the methods of
experimental economics, whether it be in the laboratory or the field. This includes studies
that exploit naturally occurring data that offer many of the controls of experiments.
3
We
generally avoid any mention of studies using hypothetical surveys, because of the
overwhelming evidence of hypothetical biasacrossmostbehavioraldomains.
4
From a theoretical perspective, we can quickly identify several behavioral moving partsin
canonical insurance contracts. The first is obviously risk aversion, which can derive from
various psychological pathways. The second is, also obviously, subjective beliefs about loss
probabilities, as well as nonperformance risk and basis risk when applicable. The third concerns
time preferences, thinking of insurance as an explicitly timedated contract: in general, I give
you a known premium now in the expectation that if something happens to me over the coming
year you will honor that contract and help me mitigate the loss. The fourth then involves the
interaction of risk and time preferences, in the form of intertemporal risk aversion. As
explained below, this is not the same as atemporal risk aversion.
Sections 1 and 2 provide helicopter toursof key issues in theory and experiments that we
view as central to evaluating the literature. Section 3 reviews descriptive behavioral experiments
on insurance, and Section 4 reviews normative behavioral experiments on insurance.
2
|
THEORY
Insurance is a staple of any classroom discussion of risk attitudes and risk management. Indeed,
it is often used to immediately explain why we should be interested in knowing the risk
attitudes of an agent. The very definition of a risk premium, as the amount of money one is
willing to leave on the table, in expectation, in order to remove risk, defines willingness to pay
(WTP) for a full indemnity insurance contract with no deductible.
And the notion of a risk premium is one of the core concepts that different theories of risk
preferences actually agree on. Expected Utility Theory (EUT) posits a psychological pathway in
which aversion to variability drives a risk preference, where variability can be much more than
just variance. Rankdependent utility (RDU) posits an additional psychological pathway in
2
General discussions of the methodological implication of a theoretical behavioral research are provided by Harrison (2013, 2014a, 2014b) and Spiegler (2019).
3
Harrison and List (2004) carefully review the taxonomy of different types of experiments. The dictionary always provides a useful check on semantic
confusions. Consider the Oxford English Dictionary (Second Edition), and the definitions of the noun experimentin science: An action or operation
undertaken in order to discover something unknown, to test a hypothesis, or establish or illustrate some known truth.There is no direct mention of
randomization or causality. The verb controlis defined in the following manner: To exercise restraint or direction upon the free action of; to hold sway
over, exercise power or authority over; to dominate, command.So the word means something more active and interventionist than is suggested by its
colloquial clinical usage. Control can include such mundane things as ensuring sterile equipment in a chemistry lab, to restrain the free flow of germsand
unwanted particles that might contaminate some test. When controls are applied to human behavior, we are reminded by this definition that someones
behavior is being restrained to be something other than it would otherwise be if the person were free to act. Thus, we are immediately on alert to be
sensitive, when studying responses from a controlled experiment, to the possibility that behavior is unusual in some respect. The reason is that the very
control that defines the experiment may be putting the subject on an artificial margin. Even if behavior on that margin is not different than it would
otherwise be without the control, there is the possibility that constraints on one margin may induce effects on behavior on unconstrained margins. This
point is exactly the same as the one made in the theory of the second bestin public policy. If there is some immutable constraint on one of the margins
defining an optimum, it does not automatically follow that removing a constraint on another margin will move the system closer to the optimum.
4
See Cummings, Harrison, and Rutström (1995); Cummings, Ellot, Harrison, and Murphy (1997); and Harrison (2006a, 2014c) for evidence on hypothetical bias
across a range of domains and elicitation methods. There remains a limited role for hypothetical surveys, to explore tentative hypotheses quickly and cheaply,
and as statistical complements to incentivized responses that can be used to calibrate hypothetical responses and correct for biases. See Blackburn, Harrison,
and Rutström (1994) and Harrison (2006b).
134
|
HARRISON AND NG
which probability optimism or pessimism can augment, positively or negatively, any risk
premium due to an aversion to variability. And Cumulative Prospect Theory (CPT) posits yet
another psychological pathway on top of these, where sign dependence relative to some
reference point affects risk preferences. All agree on the same risk premium, and simply
decompose it differently.
Important extensions to these basic insights include considerations of downside risk
aversion that differs from the loss aversion of CPT, and is related to literature on higher
order risk preferences; considerations of regretor disappointmentthat can arise from
insurance decisions and outcomes; and allowance for multiattribute risk aversion, across
insurance product lines or between foreground and background risk.
Theories of time preference range from Exponential discounting to Hyperbolic and Quasi
Hyperbolic models. The differences can best be understood by thinking of the lender of money
as having some cost to not having her money for a time period. Exponential discounting
assumes a constant variable cost with respect to time and no fixed cost; Hyperbolic discounting
assumes a declining variable cost with respect to time and no fixed cost, and QuasiHyperbolic
discounting assumes a fixed cost and a constant variable cost.
5
An alternative approach from
psychology is to view the perception of time horizon as subjective: if the agent perceives time
units contracting as the horizon gets longer, declining discount rates will arise.
Virtually all theories of time preference assume an additive intertemporal utility function, in
which utility over time is a discount factor weighted sumof utility for each distinct period.In this
respect, the alternative theories behind the discount factor tend to agree, and also use an additive
intertemporal utility function. This seemingly technical assumption, however, has dramatic
implications for behavior: it implies that agents are neutral toward risk over time, even if they are
averse to risk at a point in time. In words, agents might be temporally risk neutral to risk resolved
at a point in time but must be intertemporally risk averse to risk resolved over time.
6
Anasty
corollary is that atemporal risk preferences and time preferences are formally tiedat the hip,in
the sense that the intertemporal elasticity of substitution must be equal to the inverse of relative
risk aversion. This corollary sits uncomfortably with intuition and the stylized data one
encounters in aggregate data, forcing problematic calibrations in macroeconomic models. A
simple resolutionof this impasse is to allow nonadditive intertemporal utility functions, such that
interactions between atemporal risk aversion between time periods matter to the agent: see
Andersen, Harrison, Lau, and Rutström (2018) for a review of the theory.
The static theory of subjective beliefs is dominated by subjective expected utility (SEU),
which assumes that agents behave as if satisfying the reduction of compound lotteries (ROCL).
The effect is that nondegenerate subjective belief distributions can be replaced by the weighted
average belief, and then EUT applied as usual. It is noteworthy that SEU does not assume that
the subjective belief distributions that agents hold satisfy Bayes Rule when updated over time,
despite Savage being a staunch advocate for each. Bayes Rule is a separate model of (dynamic)
risk perception, which may or may not apply with SEU. Relaxations of ROCL that still assume
that the agent has a welldefined subjective belief distribution characterize uncertainty, and
models of decisionmaking that do not assume a welldefined subjective belief distribution
characterize ambiguity: see Harrison (2011) for an exposition.
5
So stated, the QuasiHyperbolic assumption is that these fixed costs are some constant fraction of the loan principal, which has the implication that it
stays important for all magnitudes of the loan. An alternative is to assume some fixed cost in terms of money, which of course declines in importance as
loan magnitudes increase.
6
This is a different matter than the agent having preferences over when risk is resolved.
HARRISON AND NG
|
135

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT