Bargaining and Bicameralism

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/lsq.12179
Date01 February 2018
Published date01 February 2018
AuthorGiri Parameswaran
GIRI PARAMESWARAN
Haverford College
Bargaining and Bicameralism
In bicameral legislatures, the protection of small states often motivates the malap-
portionment of the upper house. Using a legislative bargaining model, I show that
malapportionment may produce the opposite effect. Under unicameralism, same-state
legislators are shown to not inherently be coordinated to cooperate, diminishing the fear
of a big-state conspiracy. By contrast, under bicameralism, preference complementarities
enable upper-house legislators to effectively coordinate their state delegations, and
this skews the expected allocation in favor of big states. Hence, unless bicameralism
significantly increases their agenda power, small states will fare even worse under
bicameralism whenever they are disadvantaged under unicameralism.
The equality of representation in the Senate is ...evidently the result of a compromise
between the opposite pretensions of the large and small States. ... A government
founded on principles more consonant tothe wishes of the larger States, is not likely to
be obtained from the smallerStates.
— James Madison, Federalist No. 62
Bicameralism is an institutional feature common to many legisla-
tures around the world. In almost all bicameral systems, legislators in the
lower house represent districts of roughly equal size by population (Tsebe-
lis and Money 1997), ref‌lecting the principle of equal representation. By
contrast, representation in the upper house is often intentionally malappor-
tioned to benef‌it particular constituencies.
1
For example, a malapportioned
upper house that gives equal representation to states or provinces has the
obvious effect of overrepresenting regions with smaller populations.
In the United States, the overrepresentation of small states in the
upper house resulted from a compromise with the small states, who
feared that their interests would be ignored in the popular chamber where
a few large states could command majorities between th emselves. A sim-
ilar compromise, to entice smaller states to join the federation, informed
the design of the Australian Senate. The logic seems straightforward:
overrepresentation of small states in the upper house protects them
against usurpation of the policy agenda by the larger states. Implicit in
the argument’s logic is the expectation that state delegations in a
LEGISLATIVE STUDIES QUARTERLY, 43, 1, February 2018 101
DOI: 10.1111/lsq.12179
V
C2017 Washington University in St. Louis
unicameral legislature will likely vote as a coordinated unit. This, in
turn, requires that the interests of legislators from the same state suff‌i-
ciently overlap, so that a policy that is held to be desirable by some
legislators from a given state will likely be held desirable by most or all
legislators from that state.
But this is a strong assumption. Policies may, after all, benef‌it vot-
ers in some parts of a state but not others. A policy to f‌inance public
transit infrastructure, for example, will likely be supported by legislators
representing districts in New York City but is unlikely to be of much
value to legislators representing districts upstate. The interests of people
in different electoral districts need not coincide simply because those dis-
tricts are located within the same state. (Thorpe [2010] f‌inds, for
example, that geographic disparities in the allocation of defense contracts
are tied to local, rather than statewide, economic conditions.) Over a
variety of policy issues, local interests may well be most salient in deter-
mining legislator behavior.
This article investigates the claim that bicameralism provides an
advantage to small states. I assume that legislators are concerned with
the interests of their immediate constituency, so that parochial and state
interests do not necessarily coincide. I show that, contrary to conven-
tional wisdom, bicameralism does not necessarily improve the welfare
of small states and may have the unintended consequence of harming
them. Moreover, bicameralism will tend to worsen outcomes for small
states precisely when those states would already have been disadvan-
taged under unicameralism. Hence, the case for bicameralism as a check
against policy usurpation by big states may be mistaken and warrants
further examination.
To study this question, I adapt the bargaining framework in Baron
and Ferejohn (1989) to model decision making in a bicameral legisla-
ture. The legislature must allocate a f‌ixed surplus among various
districts. Each district is contained within a state, and small states contain
fewer districts than big states. Representation in the lower house is by
district, while representation in the upper house is by state. Lower-house
legislators seek to maximize the allocation to their district alone, while
upper-house legislators seek to maximize the total allocation to the dis-
tricts within their state. If recognized, a legislator will propose an
allocation that maximizes funding to her constituency while earning the
support of majorities in both chambers. In equilibrium, the proposal will
target districts whose representatives are “cheap”—that is, who will
demand fewer concessions before supporting a proposal. The price of
legislators in turn depends on the size of the allocation they expect to
receive. Legislators who rationally expect to receive more will be more
102 Giri Parameswaran
demanding than those who expect to receive less. Since allocating funds
to a given district benef‌its both the legislator representing that district
and the legislator representing the associated state, there are complemen-
tarities between the preferences of lower- and upper-house legislators
from the same state. This complementarity will be crucial to the analysis
that follows.
The main insight of this article is as follows: Under unicameralism,
while it is possible for big-state legislators to privilege one another when
forming coalitions (to the detriment of small states), such behavior
would often not be in their best interest. Indeed, a big-state legislator
may f‌ind it more rewarding to collaborate with small-state legislators,
especially if they are cheaper. Hence, under unicameralism, legislators
from the same state are not inherently coordinated to work together; they
are not natural coalition partners. Additionally, if the concern of policy
usurpation by big states is well founded, then it must be that small-state
legislators are cheaper coalition partners, since they would be expected
to gain less in the bargaining process. Hence, the fear that big states will
conspire against small states is least compelling precisely in those cases
when small states are expected to fare poorly.
Now, consider a bicameral legislature. The incentives for lower-
house legislators are analogous to the unicameral case. However, the
incentives for upper-house legislators differ markedly, since they are
concerned with the total allocation across their state. (This is consistent
with the empirical f‌indings in Lee [2004] and Lazarus and Steigerwalt
[2009] that the statewide interests of upper-house legislators differ from
the parochial interests of lower-house legislators from the same state.)
When recognized, an upper-house legislator will allocate funds across
each of the districts within his state. Given the complementarity in pref-
erences, this naturally earns the support of the lower-house legislators
from his state, resulting in coordinated support for policies among state
delegations. Furthermore, this coordinated support from the proposer’s
delegation reduces the number of out-of-state legislators upon whom the
proposer must expend resources to build a winning coalition. Since big-
state delegations are larger than small-state delegations, they are then
able to retain more resources within their own state, thus skewing the
distribution in their favor. I refer to this as the reduced-requirement
effect. By introducing state-level representatives, bicameralism has the
unintended consequence of creating incentives for precisely the sort of
coordinated behavior that generated the concern of policy usurpation by
big states under unicameralism.
Of course, by requiring that proposals receive majority support in
the upper house, where small-state legislators are more numerous,
103Bargaining and Bicameralism

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT