Attending to inattention: Identification of deadweight loss under nonsalient taxes

Published date01 February 2020
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jpet.12401
Date01 February 2020
AuthorBenjamin Glass,Giacomo Brusco
J Public Econ Theory. 2020;22:524. wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/jpet © 2019 Wiley Periodicals, Inc.
|
5
Received: 6 May 2019
|
Accepted: 16 August 2019
DOI: 10.1111/jpet.12401
ORIGINAL ARTICLE
Attending to inattention: Identification of
deadweight loss under nonsalient taxes
Giacomo Brusco
1
|
Benjamin Glass
2
1
Department of Economics, University of
Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan
2
Department of Economics, Pennsylvania
State University, University Park,
Pennsylvania
Correspondence
Giacomo Brusco, Department of
Economics, University of Michigan, Ann
Arbor, MI 48109.
Email: giacomo.brusco@gmail.com
Abstract
Recent developments in behavioral public economics
have shown that heterogeneous biases prevent point
identification of deadweight loss. We replicate this result
for an arbitrary (closed) consumption set, whereas
previous results on heterogeneous attention focused on
binary choice. We find that one can bound the efficiency
costs of taxation based on aggregate features of demand.
When individuals have linear demand functions, the
bounds for deadweight loss are easy to calculate from
linear regressions.
1
|
INTRODUCTION
Taxing a good results in a loss of economic efficiency whenever it distorts equilibrium behavior
away from the Pareto optimum. To the extent that agents do not notice a tax, the burden of the
tax is exacerbated by the fact that agents cannot adjust the behavior to protect themselves from
the tax. However, the burden of the tax in excess of government revenue, or deadweight loss, is
mitigated when agents do not pay attention to the tax: if consumers pay the tax without noticing
it, they are effectively transferring some of their income to the government in a lump sum.
Chetty, Looney, and Kroft (2009; henceforth CLK) were the first to make these points. In
addition to their theoretical contributions, they also showed that consumers in the United
States, where sales tax is applied at the register rather than included on the prices displayed on
shelves (or sticker prices), tend to underreact to sales taxes.
While CLK (2009) focuses on the case of homogeneous attention, recent work by Taubinsky
and ReesJones (2018; henceforth TRJ) has noted that introducing the possibility of
heterogeneous attention may prevent the computation of deadweight loss from aggregate data.
If each person faced a different tax rate when buying a certain good, understanding welfare
effects would require us to study not only aggregate demand, but the demand of every
individual. Imposing a high tax on low elasticity individuals and a low tax on high elasticity
individuals would have a very different effect on welfare than doing the opposite. A similar
reasoning applies when all agents face the same tax rate, but perceive different tax rates. TRJ
(2018) find that allowing for heterogeneous attention introduces an issue of allocative
inefficiency that is normally absent from the study of the welfare effects of taxation. In a world
of heterogeneous attention, there is no guarantee that the individuals who end up consuming
the good are the ones who value it the most.
TRJ (2018) make these points in a binary choice model. This is wellsuited to their
experiment, in which people are choosing whether or not to buy a certain object, but their proof
does not generalize trivially. Given the predominance of continuous choice settings in much of
the literature on tax salience, including CLKs seminal paper, this motivates us to study the
issue further.
We begin by developing a model of choice under misperceived prices with an arbitrary
closed consumption set, and develop our welfare measure: compensating variation due to the
tax, net of tax revenue. Bernheim and Rangel (2009) laid the foundations of welfare analysis
with behavioral agents. Our model is similar to the models of CLK (2007, 2009) and TRJ (2018),
but we slightly modify the treatment of income effects, along the lines of Gabaixs (2014) model
of rational inattention. In the absence of income effects, our model of choice for an individual
agent is essentially equivalent to the model in CLK (2009), except that we allow for arbitrary
consumption sets. Our model is also similar to the model of Chetty (2009), but for the fact that
we specify a particular way in which behavioral agents maximize utility. While this does not
impose severe restrictions on behavior, it offers a useful framework when we move on to
identification. We confirm that some of the major results in CLK (2009) and TRJ (2018) hold
quite broadly: inattention to taxes increases the size of the loss in consumer surplus, but
decreases the size of deadweight loss; attention heterogeneity amplifies deadweight loss, and
invalidates CLKs sufficient statistic approach.
The main contribution of this paper is to generalize TRJs nonidentification result to an
arbitrary closed choice set. We show that an econometrician who only observes aggregate
consumption data can only determine the true value of aggregate deadweight loss to lie on an
interval. These bounds were first noted by TRJ (2018) in their proposition A.2. We find these
bounds hold generally and propose to use them as a novel empirical tool.
The lower bound for deadweight loss is the calculation one would perform in the case of a
representative consumer. Since the loss in efficiency is a convex function of the perceived tax
rate, the calculation of deadweight loss from one perceived taxinclusive price consistent with
aggregate demand will generically underestimate deadweight loss. Heterogeneity in tax salience
creates heterogeneity in perceived netoftax prices, which creates an allocative inefficiency
across consumers. As the calculation with a representative consumer only accounts for
inefficiency from aggregate foregone consumption due to the tax, it will underestimate excess
burden. However, in the case in which all agents pay the same amount of attention to the tax,
there is no allocative inefficiency between consumers, and so performing the calculation as with
a representative consumer yields the correct value for deadweight loss. The formula for this
lower bound to deadweight loss is an extension of formulas provided by CLK (2009) and TRJ
(2018).
Following TRJ (2018), we obtain an upper bound for deadweight loss by letting the
econometrician assume that tax salience has support on a known bounded nonnegative
interval. The upper bound comes from maximizing perceived price heterogeneity, again
exploiting the convexity of deadweight loss with respect to the perceived tax. This is achieved by
positing that agents have either zero or maximal salience. Generalizing introduces two
additional considerations in calculating the upper bound for deadweight loss. One, a
distribution yielding the upper bound for deadweight loss assigns high tax salience precisely
6
|
BRUSCO AND GLASS

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT