Ambiguity and Insurance: Capital Requirements and Premiums

AuthorOliver Walker,Simon Dietz
Date01 March 2019
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/jori.12208
Published date01 March 2019
©2017 The Journal of Risk and Insurance. Vol.86, No. 1, 213–235 (2019).
DOI: 10.1111/jori.12208
Ambiguity and Insurance: Capital Requirements
and Premiums
Simon Dietz
Oliver Walker
Abstract
Many insurance contracts are contingent on events such as hurricanes, terror-
ist attacks, or political upheavals, whose probabilities areambiguous. This ar-
ticle offers a theory to underpin the largebody of empirical evidence showing
that higher premiums are charged under ambiguity. We model a (re)insurer
that maximizes profit subject to a survival constraint that is sensitive to the
range of estimates of the probability of ruin, as well as the insurer’s attitude
toward this ambiguity.We characterize when one book of insurance is more
ambiguous than another and general circumstances in which a more am-
biguous book requires at least as large a capital holding. We subsequently
derive several explicit formulae for the price of insurance contracts under
ambiguity,each of which identifies the extra ambiguity load.
Introduction
Many (re)insurance contracts are contingent on events such as hurricanes, terrorist
attacks, or political upheavals, whose probabilities are not known with precision.
Such contracts are said to be subject to “ambiguity.” There may be several reasons
why contracts are subject to ambiguity, including a lack of historical, observational
data, and the existence of competing theories, proffered by competing experts and
formalized in competing forecasting models, of the causal processes governing events
that determine their value. For example, ambiguity is a salient feature in the insurance
of catastrophe risks such as hurricane wind damage to property in the Southeastern
United States. Here, historical data on the most intense hurricanes are limited, and
there are competing models of hurricane formation (Knutson et al., 2008; Bender et al.,
Simon Dietz is at the ESRC Centre for Climate Change Economics and Policy, Grantham Re-
search Institute on Climate Change and the Environment, and Department of Geography and
Environment, London School of Economics and Political Science. Dietz can be contacted via
e-mail: s.dietz@lse.ac.uk. Oliver Walker is at ESRC Centre for Climate Change Economics and
Policy and Grantham Research Institute on Climate Change and the Environment, London
School of Economics and Political Science and Vivid Economics Ltd., London. We are very
grateful to the editor,three anonymous referees, Pauline Barrieu, and Trevor Maynard for com-
ments on previous drafts. We would like to acknowledge the financial support of Munich Re,
the United Kingdom’s Economic and Social Research Council and the Grantham Foundation
for the Protection of the Environment. The usual disclaimer applies.
213
214 The Journal of Risk and Insurance
2010; Ranger and Niehoerster, 2012). This ambiguity is increasedby the potential role
of climate change in altering the frequency, intensity, geographical incidence, and
other features of hurricanes.
There is by now a body of evidence to show that, faced with offering a contract under
ambiguity, insurers increase their premiums, limit coverage, or are unwilling to pro-
vide insurance at all. Much of the academic evidence is survey based: actuaries and
underwriters from insurance and reinsurance companies are asked to quote prices for
hypothetical contracts in which the probabilities of loss are alternatively known or
unknown (Hogarth and Kunreuther,1989, 1992; Kunreuther, Hogarth, and Maszaros,
1993; Kunreuther et al., 1995; Cabantous, 2007; Kunreuther and Michel-Kerjan, 2009;
Cabantous et al., 2011). Their responses reveal that prices for contracts under ambi-
guity exceed prices for contracts without ambiguity and with equivalent expected
losses, which is consistent with ambiguity aversion1and, thus, in line with a much
larger body of evidence on decision making, starting with Ellsberg’s classic thought
experiments on choices over ambiguous and unambiguous lotteries (Ellsberg, 1961).
In the industry,one can find guidance that insurers should increase their “prudential
margins” (i.e., capital holdings) under ambiguity (e.g., Barlow et al., 1993) and below
we explain how this leads to higher premiums.
Yet, despite the evidence, there is seemingly little theoretical work that can explain
or formally motivate these ambiguity loadings. In this article, we seek to fill this hole
by offering a formal analysis of the connection between, on the one hand, ambiguous
information about the performance of a book of insurance and, on the other hand, the
premium charged for a new contract. We do so via the capital held against the book:
our starting point is a well-known model of the price of insurance, according to which
the objective is to maximize expected profits subject to a survival constraint (thus in
the tradition of Stone, 1973), which is imposed by managerial or regulatory fiat out
of concern for ensuring solvency or avoiding a downgrading of credit. An example
of such a constraint, imposed by regulation, is the European Union’s new Solvency
II Directive (where it is called a Solvency Capital Requirement). Our twist is that the
capital held is sensitive to the range of estimates of the probability of ruin and to the
insurer’s attitude toward ambiguity in this sense.
Based on recent contributions to the theory of decision making under ambiguity, we
characterize circumstances in which one book of insurance is “more ambiguous” than
another, and establish general conditions under which more ambiguous books entail
higher capital holdings under our capital-setting rule. We then use the rule to de-
rive pricing formulae for ambiguous contracts in a way that isolates the additional
ambiguity load, distinct from the more familiar risk load. We examine the properties
of the ambiguity load under different assumptions about the insurer’s information:
it is shown to depend on the ambiguity of the contract being priced, as well as the
insurer’s ambiguity aversion. It also depends on the relationship between the am-
biguity of the new contract and the ambiguity of the preexisting book, and under
some circumstances it can interact with the coventional risk load. We hope that these
1We give formal definitions of ambiguity, ambiguity aversion, and related concepts later.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT