Absolving God’s Laws: Thomas Hobbes’s Scriptural Strategies

AuthorAlison McQueen
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1177/00905917221092424
Published date01 October 2022
Date01 October 2022
Subject MatterArticles
https://doi.org/10.1177/00905917221092424
Political Theory
2022, Vol. 50(5) 754 –779
© The Author(s) 2022
Article reuse guidelines:
sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/00905917221092424
journals.sagepub.com/home/ptx
Article
Absolving God's Laws:
Thomas Hobbes's
Scriptural Strategies
Alison McQueen1
Abstract
Thomas Hobbes tells us that he wrote Leviathan to “absolve the divine
laws” of the charge that they justify rebellion. This article interprets the
argumentative strategy of the second half of Leviathan in light of this intention.
Over the course of his three major political works, Hobbes develops a
convergent argument to absolve God’s laws. This strategy of judicial rhetoric
relies on using multiple independent claims in the hope that one’s audience
finds at least one of them persuasive. This was a risky strategy for Hobbes
that angered his critics. The strategy also reveals something about what sort
of philosopher Hobbes was and how we ought to approach his work.
Keywords
Hobbes, religion, scripture, Leviathan, rhetoric, strategy
Introduction
Thomas Hobbes tells us that political circumstances compelled him to write
Leviathan (1651). In the spring of 1646, he was living in a self-imposed exile
in Paris as the civil war raged on in Britain. As Charles I was surrendering to
1Stanford University, Stanford, CA, USA
Corresponding Author:
Alison McQueen, Stanford University, 616 Serra St, Encina Hall W, Rm 100, Stanford, CA
94305, USA.
Email: amcqueen@stanford.edu
1092424PTXXXX10.1177/00905917221092424Political TheoryMcQueen
research-article2022
McQueen 755
the Scots, Hobbes was immersed in work on De Corpore. His plan was that
this would be the first of three sections in his Elements of Philosophy. The
work was going slowly. Hobbes hoped to make substantial progress during a
visit to the south of France. But in July the young prince Charles and his
entourage arrived in Paris, and Hobbes was asked to serve as his mathematics
tutor. Hobbes’s pastoral productivity would have to be postponed.
But the prince’s tuition was not the only thing tearing Hobbes away from
his systematic philosophy. The young Charles and his men had brought fresh
news of Royalist defeats, which the king’s enemies were interpreting as evi-
dence of God’s support for the Parliamentarian cause. Hobbes tells us that he
“could not bear to hear such terrible crimes attributed to the commands of
God.” He set De Corpore aside and, determined to write something at once to
“absolve the divine laws,” he turned his attention to the work that would
become Leviathan (Hobbes 1839, xcii).1
The book is rarely interpreted (and even more rarely taught) in a way that
acknowledges these intentions.2 Failing to listen to Hobbes’s own reasons for
writing Leviathan has two dire interpretive consequences. First, it makes it
too easy to avoid the entire second half of Leviathan. This portion of the work
consists entirely of exegetical and theological claims supported by scriptural
interpretation. Many twentieth-century Hobbes scholars found some way to
dismiss the second half of Leviathan by claiming either that its arguments
“aren’t really there” or that Hobbes “didn’t really mean them” (Pocock 1970,
161–62).
Interpreters with the first attitude have tended to be analytic philosophers.
On their view, Hobbes’s religious arguments are there to reassure believers
who are attracted to the philosophical arguments for political obligation and
1. I adopt Quentin Skinner’s (1996, 330–31) translation here and in subsequent
quotations from this work.
2. Noel Malcolm (2012, 10–11) presents compelling evidence that Hobbes began
writing the book three years later, in 1649. However, even if Hobbes’s dating of
the composition is not accurate, there are reasons to think his account of his moti-
vations was, especially given how similar this account is to the one in the preface
to the second edition of De Cive (Hobbes 1998, 12–14). Subsequent citations
of Hobbes’s main political works, Elements of Law (EL), De Cive (DCv), and
Leviathan (L), will be in-text and take the following form: ([abbreviated work]
[chapter].[section, if applicable], [page]). The editions of Elements of Law, De
Cive, and Leviathan, respectively, used here are Hobbes (1998), Hobbes (2008),
and Hobbes (2012).

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT